Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-c47g7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-19T01:18:24.660Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

30 - Tracing Finnis’s Criticism of Hart’s Internal Point of View: Instability and the ‘Point’ of Human Action in Law

from Part VI - Critique

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  21 January 2021

Torben Spaak
Affiliation:
Stockholms Universitet
Patricia Mindus
Affiliation:
Uppsala Universitet, Sweden
Get access

Summary

Rodriguez-Blanco clarifies John Finnis’s objection to legal positivism in the shape of Hart’s theory, namely, that it is unstable because it uses the notion of an internal point of view, which does not have sufficient discriminatory power to distinguish between good and less good legal norms, between rational and non-rational court decisions, etc. Finnis’s view is that understanding a human action in law involves understanding what the point of the action is, that such understanding requires use of the Aristotelian focal meaning (or central case) methodology, that Hart’s internal point of view does not involve focal meaning and therefore cannot be used to understand the point of human actions, and that Hart’s theory is thus unstable. Rodriguez-Blanco argues that Anglophone legal philosophers’ focus in the past fifty years on Dworkin’s critique of Hart’s legal positivism has meant that they missed an opportunity to learn, through Finnis’s critique of Hart’s theory, about the philosophy of practical reason and the theory of action, and to contribute significantly to debates about normative questions, the nature of law and its relation to agency, reasons for action, and goodness.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2021

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Adler, M. 2009. ‘Social Facts, Constitutional Interpretation and the Rule of Recognition’. In ed. Adler, M. D. and Himma, K. E. (eds.). The Rule of Recognition and the U.S. Constitution. Oxford University Press: 193233.Google Scholar
Anscombe, E. 1958. ‘On Brute Facts’. Analysis 18(3): 6972.Google Scholar
Anscombe, E. 1963. Intention. 2nd ed. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Anscombe, E. 1981. ‘On the Source of Authority of the State’. Ethics, Religion and Politics: Collected Philosophical Papers of GEM Anscombe. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Aquinas, T. 2006. Summa Theologiae I-II. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Blackburn, S. 1998. Ruling Passions. Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chisholm, R. 1976. ‘Freedom and Action’. In Lehrer, K. (ed.). Freedom and Determinism. Random House: 1144.Google Scholar
Coleman, J, 2001. The Practice of Principles. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dancy, J. 2000. Practical Reality. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dickson, J. 2001. Evaluation and Legal Theory. Hart Publishing.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. 1963. ‘Actions, Reasons and Causes’. Journal of Philosophy 60(23): 685700.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. 1980. ‘Freedom to Act’. In Davidson, D.. Essays on Actions and Events. Clarendon Press: 6381.Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. 1986. Law’s Empire. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Endicott, T. 2001. ‘How to Speak the Truth’. American Journal of Jurisprudence 46: 229–48.Google Scholar
Finnis, J. 1987. ‘On Reason and Authority in Law’s Empire’. Law and Philosophy 6(3): 357–80.Google Scholar
Finnis, J. 1988. Moral Absolutes: Tradition, Revision, and Truth. Catholic University of America Press.Google Scholar
Finnis, J. 1998. Aquinas. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finnis, J. 2003. ‘Law and What I Truly Should Decide’. American Journal of Jurisprudence 48: 107–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finnis, J. 2011. Natural Law and Natural Rights. 2nd ed. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gardner, J. 2001. ‘Legal Positivism: 5½ Myths’. American Journal of Jurisprudence 46: 199227.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grisez, G. 1967. ‘The First Principles of Practical Reasons: A Commentary on the Summa Theologiae, 1–2, Question 94, Article 2’. Natural Law Forum 10: 168201.Google Scholar
Harman, G. 1986a. Change in View. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Harman, G. 1986b. ‘Willing and Intending’. In Grandy, R. and Warner, R. (eds.). Philosophical Grounds of Rationality. Oxford University Press: 363–80.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. 1994. The Concept of Law. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Holton, R. 1998. ‘Positivism and the Internal Point of View’. Law and Philosophy 17: 597625.Google Scholar
Irwin, T. 1981. ‘Homonym in Aristotle’. The Review of Metaphysics 34(3): 523–44.Google Scholar
Kenny, A. 1979. Aristotle’s Theory of the Will. Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Moran, R. and Stone, M. 2009. ‘Anscombe on Expression of Intention’. In Sandis, C. (ed.). New Essays in the Explanation of Action. Palgrave MacMillan.Google Scholar
Murphy, M. 2006. Natural Law in Jurisprudence and Politics. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Patterson, D. 1999. ‘Explicating the Internal Point of View’. Southern Methodist University Law Review 52: 6774.Google Scholar
Perry, S. 1995. ‘Interpretation and Methodology in Legal Theory’. In Marmor, A. (ed.). Law and Interpretation. Clarendon Press: 97135.Google Scholar
Perry, S. 2000. ‘Holmes versus Hart: The Bad Man in Legal Theory’. In Burton, S. Jr. (ed.). The Path of Law and Its Influence: The Legacy of Oliver Wendell Holmes. Cambridge University Press: 158–96.Google Scholar
Perry, S. 2006. ‘Hart on Social Rules and the Foundations of Law: Liberating the Internal Point of View’. Fordham Law Review 75: 11711209.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1999. Practical Reason and Norms. Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Rhonheimer, M. 2008. Perspective of the Acting Person: Essays in the Renewal of Thomistic Moral Philosophy. Catholic University of America Press.Google Scholar
Rodriguez-Blanco, V. 2007. ‘Is Finnis Wrong?’. Legal Theory 13: 257–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rodriguez-Blanco, V. 2016a. Law and Authority under the Guise of the Good. Hart-Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
Rodriguez-Blanco, V. 2016b. ‘Action in Law’s Empire: Judging in the Deliberative Mode’. Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 29(2): 431–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rodriguez-Blanco, V. and Zambrano, P. 2018. ‘One Myth of the Classical Law Theory: Reflecting on the “Thin” View of Legal Positivism’. Ratio Juris 31: 932.Google Scholar
Schauer, F. 1994. ‘Fuller’s Internal Point of View’. Law and Philosophy 13: 285312.Google Scholar
Shapiro, S. 2000. ‘The Bad Man and the Internal Point of View’. In Burton, S. Jr. (ed.). The Path of Law and Its Influence: The Legacy of Oliver Wendell Holmes. Cambridge University Press: 158–96.Google Scholar
Shapiro, S. 2006. ‘What Is the Internal Point of View?’. Fordham Law Review 75: 1157–70.Google Scholar
Smith, M. 1994. The Moral Problem. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Tollefsen, C. 2018. ‘Aquinas’s Four Orders, Normativity, and Human Nature’. Journal of Value Inquiry 52(3): 243–56.Google Scholar
Vogler, C. 2001. ‘Anscombe on Practical Inference’. In Millgram, E. (ed.). Varieties of Practical Reasoning. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Vogler, C. 2007. ‘Modern Moral Philosophy Again: Isolating the Promulgation Problem’. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society: 347–62.Google Scholar
Wallace, R. J. 2014. ‘Practical Reason’. In Zalta, E. N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/practical-reason/.Google Scholar
Zambrano, P. 2015. ‘Fundamental Principles, Realist Semantics and Human Action’. Rechtstheorie: 323–45.Google Scholar
Zipursky, B. 2006. ‘Legal Obligations and the Internal Aspect of Rules’. Fordham Law Review 75: 1229–53.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×