Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-wg55d Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-08T11:02:52.741Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Introduction

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 February 2010

Andrew Brook
Affiliation:
Professor of Philosophy and Director, Institute of Cognitive Science, Carleton University
Pete Mandik
Affiliation:
Assistant Professor of Philosophy and Coordinator, Cognitive Science Lab, William Paterson University
Andrew Brook
Affiliation:
Carleton University, Ottawa
Kathleen Akins
Affiliation:
Simon Fraser University, British Columbia
Get access

Summary

A small movement dedicated to applying neuroscience to traditional philosophical problems and using philosophical methods to illuminate issues in neuroscience began 20–25 years ago and has been gaining momentum ever since. The central thought behind it is that certain basic questions about human cognition, questions that have been studied in many cases for millennia, will be answered only by a philosophically sophisticated grasp of what contemporary neuroscience is teaching us about how the human brain processes information.

The evidence for this proposition is now overwhelming. The philosophical problem of perception has been transformed by new knowledge about the vision systems in the brain. Our understanding of memory has been deepened by knowing that two quite different systems in the brain are involved in short- and long-term memory. Knowing something about how language is implemented in the brain has transformed our understanding of the structure of language, especially the structure of many breakdowns in language. And so on. On the other hand, a great deal is still unclear about the implications of this new knowledge of the brain. Are cognitive functions localized in the brain in the way assumed by most recent work on brain imaging? Does it even make sense to think of cognitive activity being localized in such a way? Does knowing about the areas active in the brain when we are conscious of something hold any promise for helping with long-standing puzzles about the nature and role of consciousness? And so on.

Type
Chapter
Information
Cognition and the Brain
The Philosophy and Neuroscience Movement
, pp. 1 - 24
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2005

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Akins, K. (1993a) What Is It Like to Be Boring and Myopic? In Dahlbom, B., ed. Dennett and His Critics. New York: Basil BlackwellGoogle Scholar
Akins, K. (1993b) A Bat Without Qualities. In Davies, M. and Humphreys, G., eds. Consciousness: Psychological and Philosophical Essays. New York: Basil BlackwellGoogle Scholar
Akins, K. (1996) Of Sensory Systems and the ‘Aboutness’ of Mental States. Journal of Philosophy 93, 337–372CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Appelbaum, I. (1998) Fodor, Modularity, and Speech Perception. Philosophical Psychology 11, 317–330CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bechtel, W., and Abrahamsen, A. A. (2002) Connectionism and the Mind: Parallel Processing, Dynamics, and Evolution in Networks. Oxford: BlackwellGoogle Scholar
Bechtel, W., and Mundale, J. (1997) Multiple Realizability Revisited. Proceedings of the Australian Cognitive Science SocietyGoogle Scholar
Bechtel, W., and Richardson, R. C. (1993) Discovering Complexity: Decomposition and Localization as Scientific Research Strategies. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University PressGoogle Scholar
Bickle, J. (1998) Psychoneural Reduction: The New Wave. Cambridge, MA: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Biro, J. (1991) Consciousness and Subjectivity in Consciousness. In Villaneuva, E., ed. Philosophical Issues. Atascadero, CA: RidgeviewGoogle Scholar
Bliss, T. V. P., and Lomo, T. (1973) Long-Lasting Potentiation of Synaptic Transmission in the Dentate Area of the Anaesthetized Rabbit Following Stimulation of the Perforant Path. Journal of Physiology (London) 232 (2): 331–356CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Block, N. (1986) Advertisement for a Semantics for Psychology. In P. A. French, ed. Midwest Studies in Philosophy X: 615–678
Bower, J., and Beeman, D. (1995) The Book of GENESIS. New York: Springer-VerlagCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brentano, F. (1874) Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint. A. C. Pancurello, D. B. Tyrrell, and L. L. McAlister, trans. New York: HumanitiesGoogle Scholar
Brook, A., and Raymont, P. (forthcoming) A Unified Theory of Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Brook, A., and Stainton, R. (2000) Knowledge and Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press/A Bradford BookGoogle Scholar
Caplan, D., Carr, T., Gould, J., and Martin, R. (1999) Language and Communication. In Zigmond et al
Chalmers, D. (1996) The Conscious Mind. Oxford: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P. M. (1979) Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P. M. (1981) Eliminative Materialism and the Propositional Attitudes. Journal of Philosophy 78, 67–90Google Scholar
Churchland, P. M. (1989) A Neurocomputational Perspective: The Nature of Mind and the Structure of Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P. M. (1995) The Engine of Reason, The Seat of the Soul. Cambridge, MA: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P. S. (1986) Neurophilosophy. Cambridge, MA: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P. S., and Sejnowski, T. (1992) The Computational Brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Clark, Andy (1993) Associative Engines. Cambridge, MA: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Clark, Austen (1993) Sensory Qualities. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Dennett, D. C. (1978) Why You Can't Make a Computer That Feels Pain. In his Brainstorms. Montgomery, VT: Bradford Books
Dennett, D. C. (1991) Consciousness Explained. New York: Little BrownGoogle Scholar
Dennett, D. C. (1995) The Path Not Taken. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2): 252–253CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Descartes, R. (1649) Les passions de l'âme, Amsterdam: Lodewijk Elsevier, and Paris: Henry le Gras. In Adam, C. and Tannery, P. (1964–1974) Œuvres de Descartes. Paris: J. Vrin, vol. XIGoogle Scholar
Dretske, F. (1981) Knowledge and the Flow of Information. Cambridge, MA: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Dretske, F. (1988) Explaining Behavior. Cambridge, MA: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Feigl, H. (1958/1967) The “Mental” and the “Physical”: The Essay and a Postscript. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota PressGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. A. (1974) Special Sciences (or: The Disunity of Science as a Working Hypothesis). Synthese 28, 97–115CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. A. (1975) The Language of Thought. New York: CrowellGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. A. (1983) The Modularity of Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press/Bradford BooksGoogle Scholar
Gold, I., and Stoljar, D. (1999) A Neuron Doctrine in the Philosophy of Neuroscience. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 22 (5), 809–830CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Grush, R. (1998) Skill and Spatial Content. Electronic Journal of Analytic Philosophy 6 (6), http://ejap.louisiana.edu/EJAP/1998/grusharticle98.htmlGoogle Scholar
Grush, R. (2001) The Semantic Challenge to Computational Neuroscience. In Machamer, Peter, Grush, Rick, and McLaughlin, Peter, eds. Theory and Method in the Neurosciences. Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh PressGoogle Scholar
Grush, R. (2002) Cognitive Science. In Machamer, Peter and Silberstein, Michael, eds. The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Science. London: BlackwellGoogle Scholar
Hardcastle, V. G. (1997) When a Pain Is Not. Journal of Philosophy 94 (8): 381–406CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hardin, C. L. (1988) Colour for Philosophers. Indianapolis: HackettGoogle Scholar
Hebb, D. (1949) The Organization of Behavior. New York: WileyGoogle Scholar
Hooker, C. (1981) Towards a General Theory of Reduction. Part I: Historical and Scientific Setting. Part II: Identity in Reduction. Part III: Cross-Categorial Reduction. Dialogue 20: 38–59CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hubel, D., and Wiesel, T. (1962) Receptive Fields, Binocular Interaction and Functional Architecture In the Cat's Visual Cortex. Journal of Physiology (London) 160, 106–154CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Jackson, F. (1986) What Mary Didn't Know. Journal of Philosophy 83 (5), 291–295CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kandel, E. (1976) Cellular Basis of Behavior. San Francisco: W. H. FreemanGoogle Scholar
Lehky, S. R., and Sejnowski, T. (1988) Network Model of Shape-from-Shading: Neural Function Arises from Both Receptive and Projective Fields. Nature 333, 452–454CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lettvin, J. Y., Maturana, H. R., McCulloch, W. S., and Pitts, W. H. (1959) What the Frog's Eye Tells the Frog's Brain. Proceedings of the IRFCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Machamer, P., Darden, L., and Craver, C. (2000) Thinking About Mechanisms. Philosophy of Science 67, 1–25CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mack, A., and Rock, Irvin. Inattentional Blindness. PSYCHE 5(3), May 1999, http://psyche.cs.monash.edu.au/v5/psyche-5-03-mack.htmlGoogle Scholar
Mack, A., and Rock, I. (1998) Inattentional Blindness. Cambridge, MA: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Mandik, P. (2001) Mental Representation and the Subjectivity of Consciousness. Philosophical Psychology 14 (2): 179–202CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mandik, P., and Bechtel, W. (2002) Philosophy of Science. In Nadel, Lynn, ed. The Encyclopaedia of Cognitive Science. London: MacmillanGoogle Scholar
McCauley, R. (2001) Explanatory Pluralism and the Co-evolution of Theories of Science. In Bechtel, W., Mandik, P., Mundale, J., and Stufflebeam, R. S., eds. Philosophy and the Neurosciences: A Reader. Oxford: Basil BlackwellGoogle Scholar
McGinn, C. (1991) The Problem of Consciousness: Essays Towards a Resolution. Oxford: Basil BlackwellGoogle Scholar
Milner, A. D., and Goodale, M. A. (1995) The Visual Brain in Action. Oxford: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Mundale, J., and Bechtel, W. (1996) Integrating Neuroscience, Psychology, and Evolutionary Biology Through a Teleological Conception of Function. Minds and Machines 6, 481–505Google Scholar
Nagel, T. (1971) Brain Bisection and the Unity of Consciousness. Synthèse 22, 396–413CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, T. (1974) What Is It Like to Be a Bat? Philosophical Review ⅬXXXIII, 4 (October): 435–450CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Newell, A. (1980) Physical Symbol Systems. Cognitive Science 4, 135–183CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Place, U. T. (1956) Is Consciousness a Brain Process? The British Journal of Psychology XⅬVII (1), 44–50CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, H. (1967) Psychological Predicates. In Capitan, W. H. and Merrill, D. D., eds. Art, Mind and Religion. Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh PressGoogle Scholar
Smart, J. J. C. (1959) Sensations and Brain Processes. Philosophical Review 68, 141–156CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stich, S. (1983) From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Stufflebeam, R., and Bechtel, W. (1997) PET: Exploring the Myth and the Method. Philosophy of Science (Supplement) 64 (4): S95–S106CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tye, M. (1993) Blindsight, the Absent Qualia Hypothesis, and the Mystery of Consciousness. In Hookway, C., ed. Philosophy and the Cognitive Sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Gelder, T. (1998) Mind as Motion: Explorations in the Dynamics of Cognition. Journal of Consciousness Studies 5 (3): 381–383Google Scholar
Eckardt Klein, B. (1975) Some Consequences of Knowing Everything (Essential) There Is to Know About One's Mental States. Review of Metaphysics 29, 3–18Google Scholar
von Eckardt Klein, B. (1978) Inferring Functional Localization from Neurological Evidence. In Walker, E., ed. Explorations in the Biology of Language. Cambridge, MA: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Weiskrantz, L. (1986) Blindsight: A Case Study and Implications. Oxford: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Zigmond, M., Bloom, F., Landis, S., Roberts, J., and Squire, L., eds. (1999) Fundamental Neuroscience. San Diego, CA: Academic PressGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Introduction
    • By Andrew Brook, Professor of Philosophy and Director, Institute of Cognitive Science, Carleton University, Pete Mandik, Assistant Professor of Philosophy and Coordinator, Cognitive Science Lab, William Paterson University
  • Edited by Andrew Brook, Carleton University, Ottawa, Kathleen Akins, Simon Fraser University, British Columbia
  • Book: Cognition and the Brain
  • Online publication: 02 February 2010
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511610608.001
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Introduction
    • By Andrew Brook, Professor of Philosophy and Director, Institute of Cognitive Science, Carleton University, Pete Mandik, Assistant Professor of Philosophy and Coordinator, Cognitive Science Lab, William Paterson University
  • Edited by Andrew Brook, Carleton University, Ottawa, Kathleen Akins, Simon Fraser University, British Columbia
  • Book: Cognition and the Brain
  • Online publication: 02 February 2010
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511610608.001
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Introduction
    • By Andrew Brook, Professor of Philosophy and Director, Institute of Cognitive Science, Carleton University, Pete Mandik, Assistant Professor of Philosophy and Coordinator, Cognitive Science Lab, William Paterson University
  • Edited by Andrew Brook, Carleton University, Ottawa, Kathleen Akins, Simon Fraser University, British Columbia
  • Book: Cognition and the Brain
  • Online publication: 02 February 2010
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511610608.001
Available formats
×