Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-cx56b Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-10-05T07:43:48.983Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Gassendi, Pierre (1592–1655)

from ENTRIES

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2016

Antonia LoLordo
Affiliation:
University of Virginia
Lawrence Nolan
Affiliation:
California State University, Long Beach
Get access

Summary

Born at Champtercier in Provence on January 22, 1592, Gassendi is best known today as the author of the notoriously hostile Fifth Objections to Descartes’ Meditations. He was also a priest, an astronomer, a humanist scholar, and a defender of Galileanism. But the achievement that earned him a reputation on par with Descartes’ among their contemporaries was the construction of a neo-Epicurean, atomist system of philosophy.

Gassendi spent his adult life in Paris and Provence, traveling back and forth between the two regularly. As a young man, he briefly held the chair of philosophy at the Université d'Aix. In 1645 he was made professor of mathematics at the prestigious Collège Royal. (This appointment was due to his reputation as an astronomer, since astronomy was a branch of mixed mathematics. However, for most of his career, he was dependent on a succession of increasingly prestigious patrons. His chief intellectual relationships were with the other members of the Mersenne circle and especially with Mersenne himself.)

Gassendi died leaving his major work, the Syntagma philosophicum, unfinished. His executors assembled the text we have from manuscripts produced over decades; this may help to explain the somewhat repetitive and disorganized nature of the almost two-thousand-folio-page Syntagma. It covers what Gassendi, following the Hellenistic philosophers, conceived of as philosophy's three parts: logic, physics, and ethics. In logic – which, for Gassendi, encompasses epistemology, psychology, and methodology – he insists upon the senses as the source of ideas and the criterion of truth. In physics – which includes metaphysics and all of the natural sciences – he argues that the world is composed of atoms with size, shape, and motion (or motive power), moving in absolute space and time. He is thus a key founder of the mechanical philosophy, although it is worth noting that in practice Gassendian physics is highly nonreductionist and almost entirely qualitative. Gassendi's ethics forms a key part of his reconciliation of Epicureanism with Catholicism, while at the same time being heavily influenced by Hobbes.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2015

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Gassendi, Pierre. 2004. Pierre Gassendi (1592–1655): Lettres Latines, 2 vols., trans. Taussig, S.. Turnhout: Brepols.Google Scholar
Gassendi, Pierre. 1981. Pierre Gassendi's Institutio Logica 1658, ed. and trans. Jones, H.. Assen, The Netherlands: Van Gorcum.Google Scholar
Gassendi, Pierre. 1972. Selected Works, trans. Brush, C.. New York: Johnson Reprints.Google Scholar
Gassendi, Pierre. 1964a. Disquisitio Metaphysica, ed. and trans. Rochot, Bernard. Paris: J. Vrin.Google Scholar
Gassendi, Pierre. 1964b. Opera omnia, 6 vols. (facsimile reprint). Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: Friedrich Frommann Verlag.Google Scholar
Gassendi, Pierre. 1959. Exercitationes Paradoxicae Adversus Aristoteleos, ed. and trans. Rochot, B.. Paris: J. Vrin.Google Scholar
Brundell, Barry. 1987. Pierre Gassendi.Dordrecht: D. Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fisher, Saul. 2005. Pierre Gassendi's Philosophy and Science.Leiden: Brill.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Joy, Lynn. 1987. Gassendi the Atomist.Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lennon, Thomas M. 1993. The Battle of Gods and Giants.Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
LoLordo, Antonia. 2007. Pierre Gassendi and the Birth of Early Modern Philosophy.Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Osler, Margaret J. 1994. Divine Will and the Mechanical Philosophy.Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sarasohn, Lisa. 1996. Gassendi's Ethics.Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×