We use cookies to distinguish you from other users and to provide you with a better experience on our websites. Close this message to accept cookies or find out how to manage your cookie settings.
To save content items to your account,
please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies.
If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account.
Find out more about saving content to .
To save content items to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org
is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings
on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part
of your Kindle email address below.
Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations.
‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi.
‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
A natural question in the λ-calculus asks what is the possible number of fixed points of a combinator (closed term). A complete answer to this question is still missing (Problem 25 of TLCA Open Problems List) and we investigate the related question about the number of fixed points of a combinator in λ-theories. We show the existence of a recursively enumerable lambda theory where the number is always one or infinite. We also show that there are λ-theories such that some terms have only two fixed points. In a first example, this is obtained by means of a non-constructive (more precisely non-r.e.) λ-theory where the range property is violated. A second, more complex example of a non-r.e. λ-theory (with a higher unsolvability degree) shows that some terms can have only two fixed points while the range property holds for every term.
Lambda calculus is a formalism introduced by Church in 1932 that was intended to be used as a foundation for mathematics, including its computational aspects. Supported by his students Kleene and Rosser – who showed that the prototype system was inconsistent – Church distilled a consistent computational part and ventured in 1936 the Thesis that exactly the intuitively computable functions could be captured by it. He also presented a function that could not be captured by the λ-calculus. In that same year Turing introduced another formalism, describing what are now called Turing Machines, and formulated the related Thesis that exactly the mechanically computable functions are able to be captured by these machines. Turing also showed in the same paper that the question of whether a given statement could be proved(from a given setofaxioms) using the rules of any reasonable system of logic is not computable in this mechanical way. Finally Turing showed that the formalism of λ-calculus and Turing Machines define the same class of functions.
Together Church's Thesis, concerning computability by homo sapiens, and Turing's Thesis, concerning computability by mechanical devices, using formalisms that are equally powerful and that have their computational limitations, made a deep impact on the 20th century philosophy of the power and limitations of the human mind. So far, cognitive neuropsychology has not been able to refute the combined Church-Turing Thesis. On the contrary, that discipline also shows the limitation of human capacities.
This handbook with exercises reveals in formalisms, hitherto mainly used for hardware and software design and verification, unexpected mathematical beauty. The lambda calculus forms a prototype universal programming language, which in its untyped version is related to Lisp, and was treated in the first author's classic The Lambda Calculus (1984). The formalism has since been extended with types and used in functional programming (Haskell, Clean) and proof assistants (Coq, Isabelle, HOL), used in designing and verifying IT products and mathematical proofs. In this book, the authors focus on three classes of typing for lambda terms: simple types, recursive types and intersection types. It is in these three formalisms of terms and types that the unexpected mathematical beauty is revealed. The treatment is authoritative and comprehensive, complemented by an exhaustive bibliography, and numerous exercises are provided to deepen the readers' understanding and increase their confidence using types.