Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-v9fdk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-09T03:28:52.140Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Moral Responsibility, Shared Values, and Corporate Culture

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  20 November 2015

James Dempsey*
Affiliation:
University of Warwick

Abstract:

Although it is unremarkable to hear a corporate culture described as ethical or unethical, it remains quite unclear what such a claim means or how it may be justified. I begin by addressing these two questions by offering an account of corporate culture as the intrinsic values that are shared by organisation members and that underpin organisational goals. I then employ this analysis to offer a new account of how moral responsibility is generated and distributed in business organisations. Since certain corporate values, or culture, will predictably promote wrongdoing by members, all those who participated in that culture will acquire a degree of moral responsibility for the wrongdoing that results. They are, we may say, complicit in the wrongdoing because they helped facilitate it. This is because, by sharing values in the way that creates corporate culture, organisation members give each other reasons for acting in line with those values.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Society for Business Ethics 2015 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Banerjee, Neela. 2002. “ENRON’S MANY STRANDS: CORPORATE CULTURE; At Enron, Lavish Excess Often Came Before Success.” New York Times, February 25. http://www.nytimes.com/2002/02/26/business/enron-s-many-strands-corporate-culture-enron-lavish-excess-often-came-before.html?pagewanted=all&src=pm.Google Scholar
Bovens, Mark. 1998. The Quest for Responsibility: Accountability and Citizenship in Complex Organizations. Administrative Science Quarterly. Vol. 20. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Cameron, Kim S., and Quinn, Robert E. 2011. Diagnosing and Changing Organizational Culture: Based on the Competing Values Framework. Jossey Bass.Google Scholar
Christiano, Tom. 2004. “Authority.” In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Zalta, Edward N. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/authority/#ConThePolAutNatRigFreArg.Google Scholar
Dawson, Rosie. 2013. “Archbishop of Canterbury Welby Warns of Bankers ‘Lynch Mob.’” BBC Website. July 22. http://www.bbc.co.uk/news/business-23330477.Google Scholar
Donaldson, Thomas, and Dunfee, Thomas W. 1999. Ties That Bind: A Social Contracts Approach to Business Ethics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Business School Press.Google Scholar
Duff, A. 1998. “Responsibility.” Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://www.routledge.com/article/L085SECT4.Google Scholar
Gilbert, Margaret. 1987. “Modelling Collective Belief.” Synthese 1.Google Scholar
Gilbert, Margaret. 1992. On Social Facts. Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gilbert, Margaret. 2005. “Shared Values, Social Unity, and Liberty.” Public Affairs Quarterly 19(1): 2549.Google Scholar
Gilbert, Margaret. 2008. A Theory of Political Obligation: Membership, Commitment, and the Bonds of Society. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Gilbert, Margaret. 2010. “Culture as Collective Construction.” In Soziologische Theorie Kontrovers: Kölner Zeitschrift Für Soziologie Und Sozialpsychologie. Sonderhefte.Google Scholar
Goodpaster, Kenneth E. 2007. Conscience and Corporate Culture. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. 1968. Punishment and Responsibility. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hume, David. 1965. “Of the Original Contract.” In Hume’s Ethical Writings, edited by MacIntyre, Alasdair. London: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Kadish, S. H. 1997. “Reckless Complicity.” The Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology 87(2): 369.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lepora, Chiara, and Goodin, Robert E. 2013. On Complicity and Compromise. OUP Oxford.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Luban, David. 1988. Lawyers and Justice: An Ethical Study. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Masters, Brooke. 2012. “What Went Wrong with a Benchmark Rate?” The Financial Times, June 12. http://www.ft.com/cms/s/0/cc8527cc-c115-11e1-853f-00144feabdc0.html#axzz2NRGwPPHT.Google Scholar
Nagel, Thomas. 1979. “Moral Luck.” In Mortal Questions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sagiv, Lilach, and Schwartz, Shalom H. 2007. “Cultural Values in Organisations: Insights for Europe.” European J. of International Management 1: 176.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salz, Antony. 2013. The Salz Review: An Independent Review of Barclays’ Business Practices.Google Scholar
Schafer, Daniel, and Marriage, Madison. 2014. “Seven Banks Face New Forex Market-Rigging Claims in Lawsuit.” The Financial Times, February 12. http://www.ft.com/cms/s/0/1bd41d00-93f7-11e3-bf0c-00144feab7de.html#axzz39hjQGKMs.Google Scholar
Sinclair, Amanda. 1993. “Approaches to Organisational Culture and Ethics.” Journal of Business Ethics 12: 6373.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
The BBC. 2013a. “Barclays Bank Chief Antony Jenkins to Waive Bonus.” BBC Website. February 1. http://www.bbc.co.uk/news/business-21294720.Google Scholar
The BBC. 2013b. “BP Oil Spill Trial Told It ‘Put Profits over Safety.’” BBC Website. February 25. http://www.bbc.co.uk/news/business-21548117.Google Scholar
The BBC. 2013c. “Barclays’ Salz Review Blames Bank Culture.” BBC Website. April 3. http://www.bbc.co.uk/news/business-22012261.Google Scholar
Vincent, Nicole. 2011. “A Structured Taxonomy of Responsibility Concepts.” In Moral Responsibility: Beyond Free Will and Determinism, edited by Vincent, Nicole, van de Poel, Ibo, and van den Hoven, Jeroen, 254. Dordrecht, NL: Springer Netherlands.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, Bernard. 1981. “Moral Luck.” In Moral Luck: Philosophical Papers 1973–1980. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar