Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-wq2xx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-23T08:37:16.517Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The authoritarian challenge: liberal thinking on autocracy and international relations, 1930–45

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 October 2022

Matthew Draper*
Affiliation:
University of California San Diego, San Diego, CA, USA
Stephan Haggard
Affiliation:
University of California San Diego, San Diego, CA, USA
*
Author for correspondence: Matthew Draper, E-mail: draper.matthew@gmail.com
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

The return of authoritarian great powers, the slowing of the democratic wave, and outright reversion to authoritarian rule pose important questions for international theory. What are the implications of an international system populated with more autocracies? This question was posed by a diverse array of social scientists, public intellectuals, and policy analysts in response to the autocratic wave in Europe in the 1920s and 1930s. We show that a series of conversations emanating from quite diverse intellectual priors – from Christian realists to international lawyers and disaffected Marxists – converged on the risks these autocratic regimes posed to democratic regimes and the international order they sought to forge. These risks included unconstrained rulers, an inability to sustain international commitments and political processes that undermined rational deliberation at home and spread disinformation abroad. The reading of this work suggests an under-appreciated strand of liberal international relations theory, and these debates have direct implications for liberal arguments about the democratic peace. Rather than theorizing why democracies avoid war, they underscore the importance of understanding why authoritarian and democratic countries are particularly prone to conflict.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BYCreative Common License - NCCreative Common License - ND
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0), which permits non-commercial re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided that no alterations are made and the original article is properly cited. The written permission of Cambridge University Press must be obtained prior to any commercial use and/or adaptation of the article.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press

The debate about the democratic peace has proven one of the most extensive and consequential in the history of international relations (IR) theory. With a pedigree that goes back to Kant, this strand of thinking was revived in the postwar period by Michael Doyle and others through an observed regularity: that democracies don't fight one another.Footnote 1 Subsequent scholarship sought to theorize this observed outcome, focusing on institutional constraints on rulers, the capacity to signal, and shared norms among other causal factors.Footnote 2

Yet democratic peace arguments suggest a corollary hypothesis: that democracies and autocracies are more likely to fight than democratic dyads. The effects of authoritarian rule on international politics, however, have received much less attention than the democratic peace.

Unfortunately, the question is neither academic nor hypothetical. Russia and China are not simply major powers; they are authoritarian major powers.Footnote 3 The Third Wave of democratization has slowed, and we are witnessing a new era of democratic backsliding and outright ‘autocratization’.Footnote 4 What implications does a greater incidence of authoritarian regimes have for world politics?

The current period is not the first time the question has been posed. The aftermath of World War I – the Wilsonian moment – appeared to usher in a new democratic order. In 1920, only three of 29 European countries were authoritarian while the remainder could be categorized as some kind of democracy, however imperfect. By 1941, democracy had collapsed across the European continent, either as a result of internal stresses, autocratic conquest, or both.

The authoritarian wave did not go unnoticed. Scholars from quite diverse intellectual backgrounds turned their attention to the international consequences. The purpose of this article is to excavate some of this history, and in doing so to identify an understudied seam of liberal IR theory that remains highly relevant for the current international conjuncture.

The first strand of work we discuss centered on a group of Christian realists – Tillich and Niebuhr the most prominent among them – that had a powerful influence on early realist thinkers. The self-interestedness of both democratic and authoritarian powers was treated as axiomatic, thus the ‘realism’ in the Christian realist moniker. While by no means a liberal, Niebuhr nonetheless gradually came to see authoritarian rule as a central challenge to international order: through adverse selection of leaders, by eliminating political and social checks on autocrats' behavior and by undermining international norms. Despite being invoked as exemplary of an emergent realist tradition, Niebuhr in fact saw domestic regime type – democracy and authoritarianism – as determinative of international order.

A second strand of debate grappled with the international consequences of authoritarian conceptions of law, with Carl Schmitt casting a long shadow over the debate. As in the postwar period, the interwar years saw an emergent push for international legalization.Footnote 5 However, students of comparative and international law showed that the new authoritarian regimes were not only skeptical of international legal constraints but rejected domestic constraints on state power as well. In the absence of such domestic checks, legal commitments were literally incredible, the opportunities for cooperation were necessarily limited and outright conflict more likely.

A final debate on the political left, exemplified in the work of Sidney Hook, addressed these issues through a different lens but with surprisingly similar conclusions. Hook's political and intellectual trajectory initially took him into Marxism; in the late 1920s and early 1930s he was a committed revolutionary. Nonetheless, he gradually came to see democracy as foundational to his socialist commitments and became a biting critic of Soviet authoritarianism. His critique ultimately rested on what might be called a ‘political epistemology’, and the relationship between authoritarian rule, objectivity, and truth itself. Unconstrained by political debate or challenge, authoritarian rulers sought to undermine not only dissent but rational discourse. Moreover, they did so not only at home but as a component of their foreign policies as well.

We start by setting the stage: reviewing both the rise of authoritarianism in the interwar period and the much wider literature from which our examples are drawn. We then turn to short outlines of the evolution of these three inquiries into autocracy and IR. We have three wider goals. First, we hope to make a contribution to the understanding of the history of IR in the interwar period and immediately after. That history is usually presented as consisting of a ‘great debate’ between idealists and realists, focusing on a handful of leading IR scholars.Footnote 6 We join recent scholarship which casts doubt on whether the liberal IR scholarship should be seen as ‘idealist’ and even whether the ‘great debate’ took place at all.Footnote 7 In each section, we close by considering the complex relationship between these arguments about democracy, autocracy, and international politics and an emergent realism. We find that the analytic lines were by no means drawn in hard-and-fast terms and that realists as well as liberals drew on arguments about the consequences of authoritarian rule.

Second, we hope to make a contribution to method. Important work has traced the evolution of thinking about IR within the academy.Footnote 8 We suggest how the history of IR theory can cast a wider net, including legal scholars, policy analysts, and public intellectuals. The arguments we catalog rested on theoretical insights, but were also highly responsive to real-world events, sought to influence policy, and ultimately had influence on American foreign policy. Ideas mattered.

Finally, we hope to draw out this somewhat distinctive way of thinking about the democratic peace. Rather than focusing on why democracies are less likely to fight, these theorists bore into the mechanisms through which autocracies posed challenges to the democracies and the international order they struggled to construct. These domestic factors included standard institutional ones, for example anticipating the later focus on credible commitment and signaling issues.Footnote 9 However, this work also took up these themes in more novel, nuanced, and expansive ways. For example, they explored the connections between institutional arrangements and norms and showed the effect of authoritarian rule on the integrity of international law. They even anticipated the current preoccupation with the relationship between regime type, disinformation, and truth and the ways in which authoritarian regimes sought to undermine democracy abroad.

Setting the stage: the authoritarian wave

Lee offers a succinct characterization of the authoritarian wave in the interwar period.Footnote 10 The challenge to democracy came in two forms. The first were the diverse domestic developments that resulted in reversions to authoritarian rule. The overthrow of Russia's short-lived Provisional Government by the Bolsheviks in 1917 – if it could be considered a democracy – represented one of the few authoritarian regime changes instigated by the left; revolutions in Germany, Spain, and Hungary subsequently failed. Yet the new autocratic regimes were a diverse lot as well, ranging from Mussolini to the ascent of Hitler in Germany, to a collection of more traditionally conservative autocracies in Hungary, Poland, Austria, and the Balkans.

The second challenge to democratic rule took the form of outright conquest.Footnote 11 Between 1939 and 1941, seven dictatorships came under direct German or Italian rule (Poland, Lithuania, Albania, Yugoslavia, Greece, Latvia, and Estonia) and seven democracies were dismantled: Czechoslovakia, Norway, Denmark, the Netherlands, Belgium, Luxembourg, and France. These regimes were subsequently ruled by Nazi governors or by collaborationist governments such as the Vichy regime in France.

How was this resurgence of authoritarianism being read by academics, public intellectuals, and policy analysts? Some of this work was monographic and devoted to particular countries, with the ‘big three’ European dictatorships – the Soviet Union, Italy, and Germany – as well as Japan attracting the most attention.Footnote 12 But the debate went well beyond the particular.

Reflective observers like Calvin Hoover, Karl Loewenstein, Hans Kohn, George Orwell, and E. H. Carr theorized the origins, political economy, and international consequences of the new authoritarianism.Footnote 13 As early as 1935, we can find whole conferences devoted to the subject.Footnote 14

The scope of these debates was wide. Among current preoccupations was the rise of mass societyFootnote 15 and the way in which new ‘political religions’Footnote 16 sought the total domination of civil society.Footnote 17 An important strand of this new work – among both mainstream and Marxist scholars – was an interest in the social psychology of authoritarianismFootnote 18 and the debilitating effects of propaganda.Footnote 19 Others directly linked authoritarian rule and mobilization for ‘total war’Footnote 20 and noted the emergence of ‘garrison states’.Footnote 21 By the end of the 1930s, an incipient community of IR scholars joined the fray, engaging in debates on the failure of Wilsonianism but also – as we will argue – grappling with the implications of the new authoritarianism.Footnote 22

A review of this entire field is far beyond the scope of what we can do here; we can at best sample from this very rich menu. But the three conversations reported here highlight a striking intellectual development. From very diverse starting points, each of these conversations explored the challenges posed by authoritarian rule not only to international cooperation and peace but to democracy itself.

The Christian realists confront authoritarian rule

We start with the Christian realists and the figure of Reinhold Niebuhr (1892–1971) in particular. This group exercised significant influence over the course of IR theory,Footnote 23 influencing realists such as Morgenthau (1904–80) and Kennan (1904–2005).Footnote 24 Dingli succinctly characterizes this Augustinian tradition as non-utopian, anti-perfectionist, and skeptical.Footnote 25 In The Children of Light and the Children of Darkness (1944), Niebuhr offered an extended critique of authoritarianism and a defense of democracy as a check on self-interested behavior, virtually his definition of the concept of sin.Footnote 26 Over the 1930s, however, Tillich, Niebuhr, and others had already developed their analysis of the international consequences of autocratic rule. Because authoritarian systems dispensed with institutional and moral restraints on the individual leaders and oligarchies that sat atop them, they were more likely to become sources of inordinate demands on other states and thus a challenge to international order.

The preoccupations of the Christian realists with international politics grew out of the profound political and moral failure of World War I. They were initially influenced by economic interpretations of international conflict, including Marxist ones. However the first Christian voices to sound the alarm on the authoritarian turn in Europe were those most directly affected by it. The German theologian Paul Tillich (1886–1965) played an important bridging role in this regard, and was among the first in this circle to use the word ‘totalitarianism’.Footnote 27 In 1932, Tillich had published his powerful Ten Theses on the critical posture the German churches should take with respect to the demands of the Nazis. Protestant theologians in the United States were acutely aware of these developments as activists such as Dietrich Bonhoeffer (1906–45), Karl Barth (1886–1968), and others sought ecumenical support for their religious resistance.Footnote 28

But Tillich's analysis of the international risks posed by authoritarian rule went far beyond his concern with the church and had a political-economic foundation. In an essay published in 1934 entitled ‘The Totalitarian State and the Claims of the Church’, Tillich traced democratic breakdown to a process he called ‘disintegration’, including class struggles that led portions of the middle class to seek protection of their privileges even at the cost of democratic rule.Footnote 29 Tillich argued that ‘the constantly diminishing latitude for the development of capitalist dynamics forces every national group to intensify its own political and economic aspirations and thus aggravate political conflicts and economic crisis’.Footnote 30

Niebuhr's early thinking on these issues also had a strong political economy component and drew on Marxist themes. As early as the late 1920s, Niebuhr had already voiced his skepticism of progressive liberal conceits, and subsequently argued that the Versailles settlement bore some responsibility for the rise of Nazism.Footnote 31 Moral Man and Immoral Society (1932) reflected a generational reaction to the progressive theology of the Social Gospel movement and the optimistic rationalism of liberals and others on the left. Moral Man explores one central theme: that while individuals might have the potential for moral transcendence, social collectives – from classes to nation states – do not. First, collectives are held together by coercion; second, they are motivated by the interests – and particularly the material interests – of those who dominate.

At this juncture, regime type – democracy and authoritarianism – played little role in Niebuhr's thinking. He even toyed with a kind of moral equivalence in which regimes of all types were capable of overreach. Democracies no less than autocracies are ultimately held together by force and democracies no less than autocracies will be motivated by opportunistic material interests. Niebuhr not only pillories the hypocrisy of American imperialismFootnote 32 but explicitly rejects the democratic peace argument that democracies are generally more pacific: ‘it is not true that only kings make war. The common members of any national community, while sentimentally desiring peace, nonetheless indulge impulses of envy, jealousy, pride, bigotry and greed which make for conflict between communities’.Footnote 33

At some time between the summer of 1938 and the end of 1939, however, events drove Niebuhr to make two intellectual moves that are of significance for our purposes here; not coincidentally, the Munich crisis falls precisely in this time frame.Footnote 34 The first was a sharper formulation of his anti-pacifist stance; the second, a theologically grounded analysis of authoritarian and democratic rule and their international implications.Footnote 35

The lead essay in his 1940 collection Christianity and Power Politics was titled ‘Why the Christian Church is Not Pacifist’; the book was published as the debate over intervention was reaching a crescendo. The theological grounding of these arguments rested on the inadequacy of the ‘law of love’ as a guide to practical action in the world. ‘It is the thesis of these essays’, he wrote, ‘that modern liberal perfectionism actually distills moral perversity out of moral absolutes. It is unable to make significant distinctions between tyranny and freedom because it can find no democracy pure enough to deserve its devotion; and in any case it can find none which is not involved in conflict, in its effort to defend itself against tyranny’. Failure to identify the authoritarian challenge to the democracies was at the core of his damning indictment not only of the Christian pacifists, but of non-interventionism and isolationism more generally. In his view, they were ‘unable to distinguish between the peace of capitulation to tyranny and the peace of the Kingdom of God’.Footnote 36

The onset of war clarified these issues, and allowed Niebuhr to focus on the underlying sources of the conflict between the democracies and their authoritarian adversaries in The Children of Light and the Children of Darkness (1944). The disabilities of authoritarian rule were traced through a consideration of anti-democratic theory, in which Niebuhr interestingly includes not only Hobbes but Luther.Footnote 37 Niebuhr's more general critique of anti-democratic theory is its excessive pessimism: ‘human desires are regarded as inherently inordinate, and human character is believed to be practically devoid of inner checks upon expansive desires’.Footnote 38 Niebuhr concludes that only democracy can ‘guide, direct, deflect and rechannel conflicting and competing forces in a community in the interest of a higher order’.Footnote 39 This ‘higher order’ is some principle of justice against which ‘the [necessary] strategies of coercion of the community are judged and prevented from becoming inordinate’.Footnote 40 Put most succinctly, democracy is a necessary condition for moral order itself, and not only at home but in the international arena as well. Authoritarian rule forecloses this possibility, not only dampening prospects for cooperation but increasing the possibility of outright conflict.

The second critique of authoritarian regimes is more familiar and centered on institutional design. In anti-democratic theory, the interests of the ruler or ruling oligarchy and the community are assumed to seamlessly converge; Niebuhr makes similar criticisms of Rousseau.Footnote 41

Authoritarian systems are guilty of ‘failing to provide checks against the inordinate impulses to power, to which all rulers are tempted’. In his critical analysis of how German authoritarianism arose and went awry, Niebuhr even offers up a qualified appreciation of Madison.Footnote 42 The absence of checks at home ultimately has consequences abroad. Just as the authoritarian regimes subordinate the individual to the collective at home, so they tend to identify the national community with universal moral principles. As a result, they make inordinate claims on other nations and ultimately resort to outright imperialism if they have the capacity to do so.Footnote 43

The critique of authoritarianism can also be understood by focusing on how Niebuhr thought democracy operated to provide checks on self-interested behavior, which went beyond the institutional arguments just noted into the realm of norms. The ‘children of darkness’ are those who know no law beyond their will and self-interest; they reflect the challenge of moral cynicism. The ‘children of light’, however, routinely underestimate how their own behavior is also motivated by self-interest.Footnote 44 Nonetheless, the ‘children of light’ accept the imperative of bringing self-interest under regulative political and social control. Democracy is conceptualized as an institutional design for doing just that. In a well-known dictum from the preface of the book, Niebuhr argues that ‘man's capacity for justice makes democracy possible; but man's inclination to injustice makes democracy necessary’.Footnote 45 In the final chapter of Children of Light, Children of Darkness Niebuhr argues – explicitly contra Hobbes – that while ‘nations are more consistently egoistic than individuals…even the collective behavior of men stands under some inner moral checks; and the peace of the world requires that these checks be strengthened’.Footnote 46

The fundamental challenge posed to the United States in the postwar period would be that facing any great power: that ‘we must seek to maintain a critical attitude toward our own power impulses; and our self-criticism must be informed by the humble realization of the fact that the possession of great power is a temptation to injustice for any nation’.Footnote 47 Following Madison, institutional design plays a key role in this regard. Democracy ‘arms the individual with political and constitutional power to resist the inordinate ambition of rulers, and to check the tendency of the community to achieve order at the price of liberty’.Footnote 48 Niebuhr extends these arguments to the international level. Despite his critique of both naive and more sophisticated versions of the Wilsonian project, Niebuhr argued for the importance of international constitutional checks on the great powers.Footnote 49 The major powers have an obligation to transcend their narrow interests, ‘embody plans for the organization of the world into their agreements’,Footnote 50 accommodate the interests of small as well as larger powers and thus reach for an international order which embodies a conception of justice.Footnote 51

Niebuhr's arguments are not simply institutional; he casts the question in a more expansive way that relates ultimately to values. Democratic countries ‘have a culture which demands self-criticism in principle and institutions which make it possible in practice’.Footnote 52 Only under a democracy can critical voices of conscience have the freedom to articulate an alternative to moral cynicism or to the overly optimistic and ultimately naive thinking of the ‘children of light’.Footnote 53

Authoritarian regimes, by contrast, lack these institutional and moral checks. Niebuhr predicted that ‘Russia will have the greatest difficulty in establishing inner moral checks on its will to power’.Footnote 54 From Moral Man and Immoral Society through The Children of Light and the Children of Darkness, Niebuhr criticizes the Marxist failure to anticipate the rise of self-interested ruling groups that ultimately dominate the Soviet system, a point we take up later in our discussion of Hook.Footnote 55 Niebuhr attributes the difficulties the democracies will have in managing the Soviet Union in part to cultural and religious factors that pre-date Communist rule. He nonetheless concludes that ‘the tendency to self-righteousness is accentuated in Russia by the absence of democratic institutions through which, in other nations, sensitive minorities act as the conscience of the nation and subject its actions and pretensions to criticism’.Footnote 56 With remarkable prescience, Niebuhr argues that even an agreement between the powers to divide the world into spheres of influence would ‘would only mitigate mutual suspicion and only slightly delay ultimate conflict’.Footnote 57

Niebuhr is often read as paving the way for a kind of realism in which the balancing of power is central and Waltz's first and second images – those relating to psychology and domestic politics – are relegated to a secondary role.Footnote 58 But Niebuhr explicitly rejected that view.Footnote 59 It is clear that Niebuhr's realism is ultimately grounded in his theological anthropology, which underlines the debilitating effects of self-interest and the corresponding risks of leaving power unchecked at the domestic level. Tillich, Niebuhr, and other Christian realists underscored how authoritarian regimes provided few checks on the impulses of their leaders, with profound and adverse implications for the prospects for international order.

Scraps of paper? Legal scholars and authoritarian conceptions of international law

A parallel conversation among international lawyers converged around similar themes, particularly the consequences of authoritarian rule for the ability of states to maintain international legal commitments. By 1938, these authors were in agreement that the absence of constraining institutions at the domestic level had international repercussions, weakening the force of international law and heightening the risk of outright conflict and war.

These legal debates have their ultimate origins in the aftermath of the Great War (1914– 18). The victorious powers attempted to deepen the scope of international legal commitments in order to prevent a recurrence of conflict. These efforts included not only the Treaty of Versailles, the founding of the League of Nations and the Locarno Treaties of 1925, but also the Kellogg–Briand Pact of 1928 and the Washington and London Naval Treaties of 1922, 1930, and 1936. As part of the same general movement, American lawyers, jurists, and political scientists also began to articulate new conceptions of international law that justified these commitments and sought to make them more binding. These efforts all focused on what was often called the ‘problem of sovereignty’. The juristic theory of the state popular in the first decade of the 20th century had set no limits on what a state might do in the pursuit of its goals. This theory not only ran afoul of a new empirical turn in the social sciences, but seemed increasingly anachronistic in the wake of the staggering losses of World War I.Footnote 60

Unsurprisingly, the new authoritarian regimes saw the Wilsonian international order as little more than a victor's justice, a view which had influential sympathizers in both the United States and Britain.Footnote 61 But the challenge posed by the rise of authoritarian regimes went deeper. These governments not only rejected external constraints on their behavior, they also rejected the domestic legal constraints that were necessary for international commitments to be binding and credible. American legal scholars began to focus their attention on how authoritarian conceptions of law were completely incompatible not only with Wilsonian ambitions but with the very idea of international law as a constraint on state behavior. As we will show, realists were quick to identify this problem and criticize liberals for their ‘idealism’. Yet the problem that both legal scholars and emergent realists identified rested precisely on domestic political developments, namely, the rise of authoritarian regimes and the associated dismantling of constraining institutions.

This strand of thinking about the relationship between authoritarianism and international legal commitments can be framed by considering the well-known tension between the international legal principle of keeping commitments once made (pacta sunt servanda) and the recognition that treaties might be abrogated in whole or in part in the face of fundamentally changed circumstances (rebus sic stantibus). The principle of rebus sic stantibus was not widely disputed prior to 1920 and even Woodrow Wilson observed during the Versailles peace conference that a state might repudiate any treaty it wished to.Footnote 62

However, this view was increasingly challenged over the 1930s by a more legalistic interpretation of interstate commitments. The leading proponent of this approach was the Austrian jurist Hans Kelsen (1881–1973), who articulated a positivist legal theory that strictly separated law from morality.Footnote 63 According to Kelsen, law should not be seen as emanating from higher ethical principles, which could potentially be used to challenge it. Rather, law should be seen as having force because it was enacted by a legitimate authority and accepted as such.

Kelsen saw international law as fundamentally of the same apolitical but nonetheless coercive character,Footnote 64 with states as a collection of actors equal under the law, existing within a hierarchy of norms.Footnote 65 A surprising result follows. The international legal order has no need of a sovereign for the law to be binding.

Realists in the democracies were quick to point out the underlying political realities: as E. H. Carr put it tersely, such law was little more than ‘a bulwark of the existing order’.Footnote 66 Hitler was more caustic, refusing to accept ‘that God has permitted some nation, first to acquire a world by force and then to defend this robbery with moralizing theories’.Footnote 67 Also not surprisingly, authoritarian states began to systematically repudiate what they saw as imposed legal commitments. For example, both Japan and Germany left the League in 1933, Germany repudiated Versailles and Locarno in 1936, and Italy followed Japan and Germany out of the League in 1937.

Yet the authoritarian challenge to international law should not be read simply as a vindication of realpolitik. The challenge was also rooted in authoritarian theories of the law at the domestic level. These arose, ironically, in response to the weakness of democratic regimes and of Weimar Germany in particular. The German jurist Carl Schmitt – who cast a long shadow over this debate – sounded an early note of skepticism about the idea of a self-supporting legal system. Schmitt argued that by making law primary and removing it from the sphere of morality, theorists like Kelsen and Hugo Krabbe had simply reified the status quo, giving cover to special interests engaged in state capture.Footnote 68 Opting instead for a natural law approach, Schmitt insisted that no matter how extensive a code of laws might be, exceptions would nevertheless arise. He identified a state's sovereign as the entity charged with determining both whether a ‘state of exception’ (Ausnahmezustand) has occurred and what ought to be done about it.Footnote 69 While law is thereby necessarily limited, the sovereign is unlimited, conceptually prior to the legal system, and unbound by it except insofar as it wishes to be. In short, in line with the juristic theory of the state, the sovereign is by definition unconstrained.

The authoritarian regimes of the interwar period were a heterogeneous lot, and they sought to ground the state's authority in diverse ways. The American scholar of international law Lawrence Preuss, for example, identified two schools of legal naturalism in Germany.Footnote 70 One made the state the primary locus of morality; the other vested this role in the Volk. In parallel, observers of the Soviet Union noted an analogous elevation of the proletariat grounded in legal positivism.Footnote 71

But the point drawn out by this cluster of legal scholars was that the effects of authoritarian conceptions of law on IR were nonetheless quite similar. By identifying a favored group as the source of moral value, any commitments that run against the interests of that group – the nation, the Volk, or the proletariat – are by definition void. Because the state also decides what counts as in the interests of these political principals, legal theories following Schmitt effectively admitted little or no check on state action whatsoever.

The implications did not go unnoticed. Arthur Steiner observed that ‘upon the activity of the State, so conceived, there can be no limitation outside of itself; the State becomes totalitarian’.Footnote 72 Nor did authoritarians hide this fact. As fascist theorist Alfredo Rocco put it, ‘the Fascists differ fundamentally from the Liberals; the latter see in liberty a principle, the Fascists accept it as a method. By the Liberals, freedom is recognized in the interest of the citizens; the Fascists grant it in the interest of society’.Footnote 73 On this understanding, the idea of a constraint or a check on the state is self-evidently undesirable, because any such constraints would simply present an opportunity for self-interested individuals to pursue their own gain (‘class self-defense’) at the expense of the collective. In addition to challenging the sanctity of law, authoritarian regimes similarly undermined the social foundations of the checks on governments that democracies provide.

These students of international and comparative law were quick to press home the wider implications for international order. As Hoover argued, the emphasis on sovereignty at all costs ‘quite naturally engenders a complex of legal conceptions in which contractual law is preferred to customary law, bilateral agreements to multilateral pacts, the sovereignty of the single state to its limitation by political international organization, arbitration and the like’.Footnote 74 Preuss noted that by emphasizing the ‘inalienable and illimitable character’ of national prerogatives in the name of the favored group, the legal naturalists effectively denied the possibility of an objective international legal system altogether.Footnote 75 He continues by noting that ‘an individualistic system of so-called “fundamental” rights leaves the solution of conflicts to force whenever any state deems that its “self-defense” or “national honor” are endangered’.Footnote 76

Preuss was not alone. The English theorist Harold Laski argued that if we assume, with Schmitt, that ‘the state has an absolute moral value beyond which we cannot go’, then ‘the validity of international law must necessarily consist in its furtherance of that value’.Footnote 77 Because only the sovereign can judge what the interests of the state are, a state need only look to its own interests when deciding whether or not to abide by a principle of international law. The American lawyer Philip Brown returned to the competing principles of pacta sunt servanda and rebus sic stantibus to make the point. While states had long relied on rebus sic stantibus to escape irksome international commitments, democracies were constrained by domestic groups with an interest in honoring such commitments.Footnote 78 Authoritarian regimes face no such constraint. As Brown observed succinctly, in authoritarian regimes, the exception (rebus sic stantibus) swallows the rule (pacta sunt servanda).Footnote 79

The New York lawyer and Republican congressman Frederic Coudert offered a concise summary of these reflections on authoritarianism and international law. ‘The existence of such [authoritarian] States, recognizing no moral limitation, no natural rights, no rights of minorities, and wholly intent upon their own aggrandizement, is incompatible with general peace and with international law. The nation that knows no law within its own boundaries, save the will of the ruler, cannot and will not, longer than necessity or interest dictates, observe rules of law founded upon mutual consent and based upon consideration for justice and the rights of other peoples’.Footnote 80

Well before 1938, it had already become obvious that the totalitarian conception of international law made the Wilsonian facade increasingly brittle. But the fiasco of the Munich agreements at the end of September 1938 exerted a clarifying effect on the international law conversation.Footnote 81 As overt conflict loomed, it was a short step to the observation that pinning hopes on international law was not only fanciful but dangerous. Legal scholars began to argue that Kelsen's positivist separation of law and morality and his banishment of the idea of sovereignty had inadvertently provided cover for authoritarian regimes to dismantle external constraints on their behavior.

It is worth noting by way of conclusion that an emergent realist thinking embraced this critique of international law, and it remains constitutive of that tradition to this day.Footnote 82 In one of his early writings after emigrating to the United States in 1937, Hans Morgenthau – a student of Kelsen's – underlined the conflict between the interwar process of legalization and the collective security arrangements embodied in the League. By 1939, many small European states were reverting to neutrality rather than upholding their League-mandated obligation to oppose aggression by committing to sanctions.Footnote 83 The reasons for Morgenthau were clear: the changing realities of power and the weakness of the League failed to provide adequate defense for the small powers to stand on principle. International law could not sustain itself.Footnote 84

Morgenthau was not alone. By 1939, other critics began to focus on the limits to what Schmitt had called ‘legalization and depoliticization’.Footnote 85 The future Secretary of State John Foster Dulles was a young legal counsel to the American delegation at Versailles in 1919. In his 1939 book, War, Peace and Change, Dulles argued that attempts to use a fleeting position of power to ‘lock in’ a favorable international system for the future could only succeed if they were accompanied by the establishment of flexible mechanisms through which new conditions could be accommodated.Footnote 86 The English diplomat and historian Edward Hallett Carr, like Dulles a veteran of Versailles, reached similar conclusions. In The Twenty Years' Crisis, Carr argued that the interwar passion for legalization had placed international law at odds with the existing balance of power, and it was precisely this mismatch that gave the totalitarian regimes cover to repudiate their international commitments.Footnote 87 Like Dulles, Carr thought that ‘[r]espect for law and treaties will be maintained only in so far as the law recognizes effective political machinery through which it can itself be modified and superseded’.Footnote 88 Echoing Schmitt, Carr argued that ‘there must be a clear recognition of that play of political forces which is antecedent to all law. Only when these forces are in stable equilibrium can the law perform its social function without becoming a tool in the hands of the defenders of the status quo. The achievement of this equilibrium is not a legal, but a political task’.Footnote 89

But the source of the disequilibrium that Morgenthau, Dulles, and Carr identify is to be found in the collapse of democracy and the emergence of authoritarian rule. Morgenthau notes that ‘the moral and political philosophy which has been the foundation of international law from its very beginning is no longer recognized by all great nations’.Footnote 90 Yet Morgenthau is clear at the outset of his analysis that it was precisely the Italian crisis of 1936 that set this unraveling in train. Thus while the realists rightly looked to changes in the distribution of power to understand these developments, it is clearly the rising authoritarian regimes – not the democracies – that had made collective security untenable.

It is far beyond the scope of this paper to resolve the historical responsibility that Wilsonianism bears for the prolonged crisis of the 1930s, including the rise of authoritarianism itself. But it is not implausible to invert the causal arrows of the early realists and to find the unraveling of the interwar order in the authoritarian turn. Morgenthau is explicit in stating that the hitherto-restricted scope of rebus sic stantibus had depended on the existence of an ‘international morality’ that was offended by abrogating international commitments. He is also explicit – as we have noted – that these principles were no longer shared, and by the authoritarian states in particular. Carr – redolent of Niebuhr – notes that the loss of democratic constraints and the consequent neutralization of civil society prevented the moral constraints from operating. Yet these arguments are little different than the wider liberal claim that regime type mattered.

Authoritarian rule not only removed institutional and normative checks at home but decreased the prospects for international cooperation and increased the risks of conflict.

Dissecting the Soviet case: the debate on the left

In Lenin's final years, and particularly following his death in 1924, the American left engaged in a sustained internecine debate over the Soviet Union. These debates have to our knowledge not been tapped as relevant to the history of IR theory, but they proved surprisingly consequential for postwar liberalism and Cold War thinking. The debates moved along two parallel but related tracks. One centered on whether the Soviet Union was deserving of continued support, censure, or even more active and direct confrontation. The second debate, however, centered on the nature of the Soviet political system and what had gone wrong under Stalin. We will show that these debates were ultimately joined, and that the authoritarian nature of the political system was ultimately linked with the country's opportunistic international conduct prior to the war and the challenges it posed to liberal conceptions of order in the postwar period.

The debate on the left engaged competing camps. Liberals such as John Dewey never had a sustained interest in Marxism in the first place, and by 1934 infatuation with the Soviet experiment was fading among them. For those in the Communist Popular Front group, by contrast, support for the Soviet Union persisted through the show trials and the Hitler–Stalin pact, revived during the war, and was even sustained into the postwar period.

A third group of intellectuals began the 1930s with a strong commitment to Marxism but ultimately became staunch anti-Communists. Sidney Hook – prolific, polemical, and widely studied – provides an important entry point. Hook was trained as a philosopher under Dewey and wrote two of the most significant treatments of Marxist theory in the United States up to that time. Hook and other left intellectuals increasingly drew on Trotsky's critique of Stalin, but pushed the critique to its logical conclusion. The suppression of democracy, within the party as well as broader society, had a number of consequences for Soviet foreign policy. Yet one centered on the effects of authoritarian rule on scientific inquiry, the arts, and ultimately truth itself. Authoritarian regimes were not only intent on suppressing dissenting voices at home, but had an active interest in muddying rational discourse, sewing disinformation and undermining democratic rule abroad. Generally neglected in the literature on IR theory, these disaffected Marxists in fact had an abiding effect on Cold War thinking about international order.

Hook's 1987 autobiography, Out of Step, is an unreliable guide to his political views in the 1920s and 1930s; although self-critical, it also shades his radicalism and commitment to revolutionary Marxism. Nonetheless, it also outlines well the intellectual milieu in which these debates took place. Out of Step underscores that the left – but not only the left – saw the causes of World War I in the contradictions of advanced industrial capitalism and its tendency toward imperialism. Virtually by definition, the Soviet Union – as a socialist country – could not be an imperialist power in the traditional sense. Moreover, it was important for those on the left for a further realpolitik reason: that it had a crucial responsibility to check the rise of the fascist powers. As Hook put it in Out of Step, ‘since a victory by Hitler spelled, according to our own program of action, war against the Soviet Union, I assumed that the Kremlin in its own interests and that of the international working class…would organize a revolution through its powerful Communist political and trade union affiliates in Germany’.Footnote 91

This hope was quickly exploded by events. The ascent of Stalin and his articulation of the theory of ‘socialism in one country’ took Soviet foreign policy in a completely different direction. The Sixth Congress of the Comintern in 1928 outlined the onset of the ‘third period’ during which capitalism was entering a terminal crisis. This approach was rooted in an assessment of the balance of political forces in Western Europe and in Germany in particular, and took a harsh stance with respect to democratic coalition-building. Social democracy was portrayed as little more than an ally of the fascist movement: ‘social fascists’ in the Comintern's colorful language. Cooperation among the political forces on the left was thus not only unnecessary but counterproductive; in the infamous phrase of the German Communist Party, ‘After Hitler, us!’ It was not until the Seventh Congress of the Comintern in 1935 that Stalin belatedly acknowledged the necessity of forming ‘popular fronts’ that would of necessity tolerate diverse political forces in the name of the anti-fascist fight.

The question for the dissident Marxist left during the mid-1930s – those who had drifted away from the Communist Party – was why the Soviet Union had become so quiescent and opportunistic. Leon Trotsky played a seminal, even charismatic, role in providing an answer, and it centered on particularities of the political regime, including internal decision-making processes and the political economy of the state apparatus. Dating from the struggle for power following the death of Lenin, through his exile in 1929 and culminating in the publication of The Revolution Betrayed in 1937, Trotsky formulated a theory of the Soviet system that exercised tremendous sway over significant segments of the American left.Footnote 92 Stripped of nuance, Trotsky argued that the expropriation of private property and entry onto a transitional path toward socialism defined the Soviet Union as economically progressive and thus worthy of defense. Yet Trotsky simultaneously railed against political developments in the country. He was not concerned with the early Bolshevik departures from more open democratic rule. Rather he focused on what he called ‘bureaucratism’, which he believed was the defining feature of Stalinism. The administrative strata were not only self-interested but had systematically stifled inter-party democracy – at least among the leadership – that was necessary to assure progress toward socialist objectives.Footnote 93

Trotsky saw these domestic developments as leading the Soviet Union away from its revolutionary roots and obligations. In his 1934 primer on the international scene, Trotsky provided a half-hearted defense of Stalin's embrace of Wilsonian principles. A nominal commitment to disarmament and the rejection of aggression were tactical necessities brought on by capitalist encirclement. However, he favored a more internationalist Soviet Union committed to revolution abroad. Trotsky was surprisingly prescient in foreseeing Stalin's opportunism and the fact that ‘an alliance of the USSR with an imperialist state or with one imperialist combination against another, in case of war, cannot at all be considered as excluded’.Footnote 94

For the truly revolutionary, however – namely the communist movements grouped under the banner of Trotsky's Fourth International – Wilsonian ideals should not be elevated to general principles. Moreover, the sources of international conflict should not be diagnosed in liberal terms. Trotsky explicitly rejected arguments that mounting international tension should be understood in terms of regime type. ‘A modern war between the great powers does not signify a conflict between democracy and fascism but a struggle of two imperialisms for the redivision of the world’.

Hook was largely in agreement with Trotsky's analysis. However, he pushed the argument about the domestic sources of foreign policy much farther than Trotsky was willing to go and his tenuous ties to the Communist Party were sundered.Footnote 95 In particular, he started to push the critique of Soviet authoritarianism in a much sharper direction.Footnote 96 At this stage, Hook remained committed to a conception of democracy which was Marxist and at best agnostic toward democratic institutions traditionally conceived. Hook's conception of workers' democracy owed a significant debt to syndicalism, seeing democracy in the workplace as the foundation for elected workers councils. In his contribution to the debates gathered in The Meaning of Marx, Hook argued that ‘the political democracy of the bourgeoisie [still] meant the social dictatorship of the bourgeoisie’.Footnote 97 Hook placed emphasis on the importance of persuasion vis-a-vis ‘intermediate classes’, but was clear that a workers' democracy would be exclusionary: it would not permit ‘a democracy for bankers, capitalists and their supporters who would bring back a state of affairs which would make genuine social democracy impossible’.Footnote 98 Moreover, he argued that the rise of fascism proved that ‘not all matters can be settled by free discussion’Footnote 99 and that ‘Communism is most likely the outcome of a revolutionary process, albeit ideally a majority not minority one’.Footnote 100

But Hook went to great lengths to distinguish a ‘workers’ democracy’ – the term he preferred to the dictatorship of the proletariat – from what he identified as the ‘dictatorship over the proletariat’. He was highly critical of a hierarchical political party in which ‘the responsible posts in the press, schools and government are filled only by party members, that no non-party workers are elected to the councils except those approved or declared safe by the party, and that all militant workers who express their disapproval of the line of the party find their way to concentration camps or worse’.Footnote 101 In ‘The Democratic and Dictatorial Aspects of Communism’ he provided a granular inventory of how the Soviet Union had deviated from Communist ideals: the assessment of economic planning and performance was vested in an unelected Party organ rather than in bodies that workers controlled; voting was not free because ballots were not secret, and in any case the Party controlled all nominations; the judiciary was completely controlled by the Party.Footnote 102 As Trotsky also had complained, administration had overtaken governance.

What was it precisely about Soviet authoritarianism that Hook found so troubling? The critique returned Hook to his pragmatist – and ultimately Deweyan – roots. A dictatorship over the proletariat would stifle the fullest freedom of discussion and criticism. For Hook, such discussion and criticism was not only necessary to check incumbents in the usual political sense. Rather, freedom of expression went to the very institutional foundations of the scientific inquiry that was necessary for material progress. Hook repeatedly called into question Marxism's pretension to be a science and the belief that it had discovered deterministic laws of history; heated exchanges with Trotsky hammered on this quasi-religious conceit.Footnote 103 Rational human action required experimentation and learning from facts. Increasingly Hook was coming to the view that achieving these objectives rested on a particular – and ultimately liberal democratic – institutional foundation.

As noted above, the Seventh Congress of the Comintern in 1935 belatedly acknowledged the necessity for a ‘Popular Front’ against fascism that would not only unify the left but draw in liberal parties as well. Coalitions in France under Blum and cooperation between communists, anarchists, and Republicans in Spain suggested a new approach to resisting fascism. In 1936, Hitler took his first significant foray against the Versailles and Locarno settlements by remilitarizing the Rhineland. The announcement of the Popular Front and the urgency of the international situation extended the legitimacy of ‘fellow traveling’ with the Communist Party.

However the Soviet show trials that started in 1936 were but the first in a succession of revelations about the Soviet Union that further divided the left and generated a more militant anti-Stalinism that would persist and deepen into the Cold War era.Footnote 104 The absurdity of the trials, the sycophancy with which the defendants responded (later memorialized in Koestler's Darkness at Noon) and increasing awareness of the extent of the purges had a powerful effect on the left.

Philip Rahv's 1938 sweeping indictment in the Partisan Review, ‘Trials of the Mind’, ends with a pox-on-both-their-houses defense of non-interventionism.Footnote 105 But Rahv took aim not only at the Soviet system – the threat of which he put on a par with fascism – but at the complicity of American intellectuals as well.

By this point in time, Rahv and Hook were not alone. The American Committee for the Defense of Leon Trotsky provided an initial focal point for these defectors. The Committee drew together liberals such as Dewey as well as those on the left who joined the path beaten by Hook. As Westerbrook puts it in his intellectual biography of Dewey, ‘the membership list [of the Committee] was a virtual roster of the American anti-Stalinist left’.Footnote 106

Hook's detailed assessment of the show trials,Footnote 107 the heated debate over means, ends, and socialist ethics, including with Trotsky himself,Footnote 108 and further reflections on Trotsky's analysis of the Russian revolutionFootnote 109 were shifting Hook's thinking in an entirely new direction: that the Nazi and Soviet dictatorships should both be seen as ‘totalitarian’ regimes. How, Hook asked in ‘Liberalism and the Case of Leon Trotsky’, can American liberals who are concerned about fascism in Germany, Italy, and Spain be indifferent to events in Russia?Footnote 110 Hook increasingly came to the conclusion that the basic premises of the Marxist theory of the state were fundamentally flawed: that the state was simply an instrument of a dominant economic class; that an authoritarian single-party system can be considered a workers' democracy; and that residual coercive powers would ultimately wither away. Hook also concluded that authoritarian rule was hardly a recent phenomenon made visible by the show trials or even by the rise of Stalin. Rather the political choice against democracy could be traced to the very inception of the Bolshevik party and its seizure of power.Footnote 111 Hook concludes his review of Trotsky by stating unambiguously that ‘no set of economic arrangements from which democratic control is absent, can ever achieve the moral and material promise of the socialist ideal’.Footnote 112

What were the implications of these controversies for thinking about foreign policy? In the period between the Molotov–Ribbentrop pact and Operation Barbarossa (August 1939–June 1941) and again in the early postwar years, critics of the Soviet Union focused on its opportunism and expansionist behavior. Even prior to August 1939, however, Hook and other critics of the Soviet Union increasingly focused on Moscow's efforts to silence debate not only at home but abroad. The political culmination of these arguments was the founding of the Committee for Cultural Freedom in May 1939. Totalitarianism was now conceived as an ideology and political form that these regimes sought to advance. The Manifesto of the Committee published in 1939 charges that ‘through subsidized propaganda, through energetic agents, through political pressure, the totalitarian states succeed in infecting other countries with their false doctrines, in intimidating independent artists and scholars, and in spreading panic among intellectuals’.Footnote 113 The threats were not just, or even primarily, military but rather political. The very existence of democracy posed a risk to authoritarian rule, a threat it sought to meet by controlling buffer states outright and by undermining the integrity of democratic rule through fellow travelers and disinformation.

We have traced a somewhat circuitous evolution in Hook's thinking about the Soviet Union that had wider resonance among other disaffected leftists. Two lines of debate – one on foreign policy, the other around a diagnosis of the Soviet political system – were ultimately joined. TrotskyFootnote 114 and HookFootnote 115 both cataloged examples of Stalin's international opportunism and Trotsky even anticipated the alliance with Hitler. Yet Hook's interpretation increasingly diverged from Trotsky's as he focused on the fundamental differences between democratic and authoritarian regimes. As he notes almost in passing in his conclusion to Reason, Social Myths and Democracy, Hitler, Stalin, and Mussolini were ‘enemies of democracy’, not only at home but on the global stage.Footnote 116 Just as Stalin sought to eliminate any checks on his power at home, so totalitarian regimes similarly sought to use transnational allies and propaganda to silence critical voices abroad. Again, the implications for international order were obvious; an authoritarian great power such as the Soviet Union was a direct threat to the democracies and had to be met with firm policies of deterrence and even containment.

In closing, it is again worth noting some important nuances this story line introduces into our understanding of the origins of postwar realism, the nature of liberal theory, and the first ‘great debate’. The ideas about the domestic sources of Soviet conduct were by no means confined to the likes of Hook. They can be found in core writings by Kennan, who had no intellectual ties whatsoever to the left. In his famous Long Telegram of February 1946, Kennan sought to outline the sources of Soviet behavior. Strikingly, Kennan completely rejects the argument that they can be found at the level of the international system: ‘…the Soviet party line is not based on any objective analysis of the situation beyond Russia's borders…it arises mainly out of inner Russian necessities’.Footnote 117 Similarly, his famous X article in Foreign Affairs in July 1947, entitled ‘The Sources of Soviet Conflict’, makes clear in its very first paragraph that those sources are to be found in the domestic arena.Footnote 118 Kennan's model of Soviet behavior is complex and has a long-historical component. But as with Hook, authoritarianism plays a central role. He argues that it is not Russia's external environment that is threatening. Rather, propaganda advances threatening images of the outside world to provide ‘justification for that increase of military and police power in Russia state [sic]’.Footnote 119

These domestic concerns nonetheless influence foreign policy. In a 1954 symposium on totalitarianism, Kennan noted that ‘real security for them lies only in the elimination of all surrounding freedom, for the knowledge of another way of life would unsettle the Russian people more than any other single factor. Hence, I think, the expansive tendency is built into the system’.Footnote 120 Just as the Soviet leadership sought to extend its power domestically, so it used the political tools outlined by Hook to limit political, ideological, and social challenges from abroad and to sow division and ultimately undermine democratic rule where it could.

Conclusion: the authoritarian challenge

This essay has sought to reconstruct several overlapping conversations about the relationship between authoritarianism, foreign policy, and international order. In this section, we touch on how the findings can enrich current debates in IR theory and with respect to the democratic peace in particular. Those debates are once again focusing on the consequences of authoritarian great powers, backsliding, and outright regress to authoritarian rule.Footnote 121 We comment briefly on the varieties of authoritarian rule as an important research agenda and how it may point to some disabilities in the authoritarian focus we have described. We close on some future directions for the study of the history of IR theory.

Liberal IR theory has long focused on a troika of causal factors: economic interdependence; international institutions, law, and underlying norms; and democratic rule.Footnote 122 Unlike the postwar democratic peace literature, however, the emphasis in the interwar debate was less on why democracies may be pacific – at least with one another – than on the challenges authoritarian regimes posed and the greater likelihood of conflict between countries of differing regime type. This anatomy of authoritarianism and its international consequences was not limited to particular cases. Rather, it sought theoretical generality and suggested an expansive menu of how authoritarian rule might be connected with foreign policy behavior and international order. These arguments ranged from standard institutional ones to more expansive formulations about the rule of law, normative order, disinformation, and even the assault on truth. As a result, these debates have a continuing relevance to liberal international theory and the complex political challenges posed by countries such as Russia and China.

Niebuhr appears closest to standard institutional constraint arguments that have been central to the democratic peace. His critique of Hobbes and Luther ridicules the idea that the interests of rulers and publics will naturally align. He suggests – as several contemporary theorists doFootnote 123 – that authoritarian regimes face greater risk of adverse selection: the emergence of leaders whose personal interests in international conflict do not align with the interests of the publics they claim to represent. However, Niebuhr's causal story is not just about formal institutions but about broader normative and moral counterweights on the exercise of power.

While Niebuhr no doubt is an important progenitor of postwar realism, he at the same time was acutely aware of the role that normative order at home has on foreign policy and the prospects for international cooperation or conflict.

The legal conversation is a quite obvious precursor to the strand of the democratic peace literature that focuses on the credibility of commitments, but emphasizes the difficulty that authoritarian regimes have in sustaining them.Footnote 124 It is an unavoidable feature of the Westphalian system that states can abrogate international commitments at any time; that fact was well recognized by those seeking greater international legalization. What struck the comparative and international legal scholars we review here was not only the authoritarian embrace of the rebus sic stantibus exception. Rather, they underscored how it was ultimately grounded in a parallel conception of domestic political order in which legal restraints were also absent. The relevance of this literature to a world populated by authoritarian regimes could not be clearer. Can China, Russia, and other autocratic countries be drawn into international regimes in a productive way or are there intrinsic limits on their capacity to cooperate?

Like Niebuhr, Hook traversed a crooked path from a Marxist theory of international conflict to one rooted more squarely in the effects of authoritarian rule. Hook harbored doubts about the Soviet political system even before Stalin's excesses were on full display. Lingering political commitments, bias, and strategic calculations of the value of keeping the Soviet Union onside hung over conversations on the left about the Soviet Union into the late 1930s. But Hook was not alone, and others on the left also came to see Stalinism not only as a contingent historical detour, but a failure rooted in the Marxist political theory more generally. Like Niebuhr, Hook initially saw Soviet foreign policy as unprincipled, and opportunistic as a result. But he increasingly focused on the way in which authoritarian regimes had an inherent interest in extending their reach. Again, the links to the current debates about authoritarian misinformation and the epistemological foundations of international order are clear.

While it is worth cataloging these contributions to liberal theory, it is also worth noting a potential downside of the democratic–authoritarian binary. To be sure, experts on particular countries were attuned to the nuances of different types of autocratic rule and understood that they could not be treated as a piece. Many of the new authoritarian regimes in Europe were quite traditional and did not have the totalizing ambitions of Stalin or Hitler, nor their disruptive power.Footnote 125 Italy, Spain, Germany, and the Soviet Union obviously exhibited quite critical differences. In assessing this literature, it is important to emphasize a point made by political scientists such as Peceny and Weeks among others.Footnote 126 Not all authoritarian regimes pose equal risks and differences in behavior might well be traced to the varieties of authoritarian rule. In this regard, the rise in the postwar period of a focus on ‘totalitarian’ regimes may have been ill conceived in important respects, missing important distinctions among authoritarian regimes of quite different types.

We turn in concluding to some implications of our analysis for the study of the history of IR theory. While scholarly attention has been heaped on Carr, Morgenthau, Kennan, and other early realists, a body of revisionist work has come to cast doubt on whether the so-called ‘first great debate’ even took place.Footnote 127 We side strongly with these doubts; the theorists we consider here were anything but ‘idealists’. But we also believe that characterizations such as those of a ‘first great debate’ may hinge in part on how underlying source material is selected. Historians of IR should expand their palette and consider a wider array of scholars, intellectuals, and policy analysts when excavating the intellectual lineages of IR theory, and of its liberal variants in particular. Early debates about regime type, foreign policy, and international order were by no means confined to the academy, nor to political science faculty in particular.

The story we trace here continued into the war. As John Ikenberry shows in After Victory, liberal voices in the postwar planning process were preoccupied with the question of regime type, and those concerns fed into debates over how to deal with Stalin in Eastern Europe.Footnote 128 Thinking about the foundations of authoritarian rule not only played a crucial role in the period we examine here, but resurfaced with a vengeance and shaped the intellectual milieu in which postwar thinking about international politics began to gel. Major postwar works on totalitarianism, including not only Arendt, but writers as diverse as Hayek, Orwell, Camus, Milosz, and Friedrich and Brzezinski all highlighted the dangers posed by unconstrained authoritarian rule both at home and abroad.Footnote 129 For good or ill, this body of work – deeply critical of authoritarian political systems – colored elite and public views of the Soviet Union and thus had an influence on Cold War thinking. This postwar history takes us far beyond what we have sought to reconstruct here, but its interwar roots constitute an important component of the history of liberal thinking about IR that remains to be told in full.

Acknowledgments

The authors gratefully acknowledge helpful suggestions and comments by Lucian Ashworth, Will Bain, Erik Gartzke, Judith Goldstein, Peter Gourevitch, Patrick Hulme, Miles Kahler, James Lee, and Kevin Rossillon.

Footnotes

2 Inter alia, Lake Reference Lake1992; Russett Reference Russett1993; Siverson Reference Siverson1995; Owen Reference Owen1995; Schultz Reference Schultz1998; Gelpi and Griesdorf Reference Gelpi and Griesdorf2001; Lipson Reference Lipson2003; but see also Gartzke Reference Gartzke1998. Reiter Reference Reiter2017 provides a review.

5 E.g. Hathaway and Shapiro Reference Shapiro and Hathaway2017.

6 E.g. Ikenberry Reference Ikenberry2006.

7 Schmidt Reference Schmidt1998, Reference Schmidt2012; Wilson Reference Wilson1998; Thies Reference Thies2002; Ashworth Reference Ashworth2002, Reference Ashworth2006; Quirk and Vigneswaran Reference Quirk and Vigneswaran2005; Osiander Reference Osiander and Schmidt2012. Bell Reference Bell2014 looks back to a still-earlier set of antecedents in the late 19th century.

8 E.g. Schmidt Reference Schmidt1998.

9 E.g. Schultz Reference Schultz2009.

10 Lee Reference Lee2016, 1–4.

11 We make only passing reference to developments outside of Europe, but Japan's actions in Manchuria in 1931 and Italy's annexation of Ethiopia in 1936 were critical preludes.

12 E.g. Hoover Reference Hoover1931; Kohn Reference Kohn1935 and Chamberlin Reference Chamberlin1943 on the Soviet Union; Lasswell and Sereno Reference Lasswell and Sereno1937; Cole Reference Cole1938 on Italy; Stein Reference Stein1938 and Quigley Reference Quigley and Ford1939 on Japan; and Neumann Reference Neumann1935; Thompson Reference Thompson1935; Brady Reference Brady1937; Boerner Reference Boerner1938 and Neumann Reference Neumann1942 on Germany.

26 Niebuhr Reference Niebuhr1941, Ch. 7.

27 Merkley Reference Merkley1975, 78ff.

30 Tillich Reference Tillich1934, 51.

31 Niebuhr Reference Niebuhr1933, 451–53.

32 Niebuhr Reference Niebuhr and Sifton1932, 221–27.

35 Merkley Reference Merkley1975, 129–39; Warren Reference Warren1997, Ch. 5; Inboden Reference Inboden2014.

36 Niebuhr Reference Niebuhr1940, x.

37 Niebuhr Reference Niebuhr and Sifton1944, 380–81; see also Niebuhr Reference Niebuhr1940, 51.

40 Footnote Ibid., 392, 394.

41 Footnote Ibid., 380–81.

42 Niebuhr Reference Niebuhr1940, 49–67, see esp. 59.

43 Niebuhr Reference Niebuhr and Sifton1944, 442–43.

44 E.g. Niebuhr Reference Niebuhr and Sifton1944, 362.

49 Footnote Ibid., 444–49.

51 Footnote Ibid., 453–54.

55 Niebuhr Reference Niebuhr and Sifton1944, 381, 387–88.

58 E.g. Rich Reference Rich1992.

59 Niebuhr Reference Niebuhr and Sifton1944, 450–51.

61 Most notably Keynes Reference Keynes1920.

62 Miller Reference Miller1969, 293.

64 Kelsen Reference Kelsen1934, 108–09.

68 Schmitt Reference Schmitt1922; see also Dyzenhaus Reference Dyzenhaus2015, 342.

69 Schmitt Reference Schmitt1922, 12–15.

72 Steiner Reference Steiner1936, 275.

73 Rocco Reference Rocco1925, 387.

75 Preuss Reference Preuss1935, 608.

77 Laski Reference Laski1935, 220.

78 Brown Reference Brown1938, 776.

80 Coudert Reference Coudert1937, 175.

81 E.g. Hoden Reference Hoden1939.

82 E.g. Mearsheimer Reference Mearsheimer1994.

83 Morgenthau Reference Morgenthau1939, 479.

86 Dulles Reference Dulles1939, 32.

90 Morgenthau Reference Morgenthau1939, 483.

91 Hook Reference Hook1987, 176.

92 See in particular Wald Reference Wald1987.

93 Trotsky Reference Trotsky1937; Service Reference Service2009, 455–64.

94 Trotsky Reference Trotsky1934, para. 43.

95 Phelps Reference Phelps1977, 77.

97 Hook Reference Hook1934b, 47–48.

100 Footnote Ibid., 66–67.

103 Hook Reference Hook1933, Reference Hook1934a and summarized fully in Hook Reference Hook1940.

104 Wald Reference Wald1987, Ch. 5.

106 Westbrook Reference Westbrook1991, 481.

108 Phelps Reference Phelps1997, 171–79.

111 Footnote Ibid., 450.

112 Footnote Ibid., 462.

117 Kennan Reference Kennan1946, 549.

119 Kennan Reference Kennan1946, 551

121 E.g. Kroenig Reference Kroenig2020.

123 E.g. Chiozza and Goemans Reference Chiozza and Goemans2011.

125 Linz Reference Linz1975, 159 et seq.

References

Arendt, Hannah. 1951 [1986]. The Origins of Totalitarianism. London: André Deutsch Press.Google Scholar
Ashworth, Lucian M. 2002. “Did the Realist–Idealist Great Debate Really Happen? A Revisionist History of International Relations.” International Relations 16 (1): 3351.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ashworth, Lucian M. 2006. “Where are the Idealists in Interwar International Relations?Review of International Studies 32 (2): 291308.Google Scholar
Bell, Duncan. 2014. “Before the Democratic Peace: Racial Utopianism, Empire and the Abolition of War.” European Journal of International Relations 20 (3): 647–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boerner, Alfred V. 1938. “The Position of the NSDAP in the German Constitutional Order.” The American Political Science Review 32 (6): 1059–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Borkenau, Franz. 1940. The Totalitarian Enemy. London: Faber and Faber Ltd.Google Scholar
Brady, Robert. 1937. The Spirit and Structure of German Fascism. London: Camelot Press, Ltd.Google Scholar
Brown, Philip M. 1938. “International Lawlessness.” The American Journal of International Law, 32 (4): 775–8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Camus, Albert. 1951. The Rebel: An Essay on Man in Revolt (trans. Bower). New York: Knopf.Google Scholar
Carr, Edward Hallett. 1939a. The Twenty Years’ Crisis: 1919–1939. London: Macmillan Company Ltd.Google Scholar
Carr, Edward Hallett. 1939b. Nationalism: A Report by a Study Group of Members of the Royal Institute of International Affairs. London: Macmillan Company Ltd.Google Scholar
Chamberlin, William. 1943. The Russian Enigma: An Interpretation. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons.Google Scholar
Childs, Harold Lawrence, ed. 1936. Propaganda and Dictatorship: A Collection of Papers. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Chiozza, Giacomo and Goemans, Hein E.. 2011. Leaders and International Conflict. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cole, Taylor. 1938. “Foreign Governments and Politics: Italy's Fascist Bureaucracy.” The American Political Science Review 32 (6): 1143–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coudert, Frederic R. 1937. “Obstacles to World Peace.” World Affairs, 100 (3): 173–5.Google Scholar
Dewey, John. 1939. “The Committee for Cultural Freedom,” New Republic, June 14, 1939, 161–2.Google Scholar
Dingli, Sophia. 2020. “Conceptualizing Peace and its Preconditions: The Anti-Pelagian Imagination and the Critical Turn in Peace Theory.” Journal of International Political Theory forthcoming. 17 (3): 468–87.Google Scholar
Doyle, Michael W. 1983a. “Kant, Liberal Legacies and Foreign Affairs.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 12 (3): 205–35.Google Scholar
Doyle, Michael W. 1983b. “Kant, Liberal Legacies and Foreign Affairs, Part 2.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 12 (4): 323–53.Google Scholar
Dulles, John F. 1939. War, Peace and Change. New York: Harper.Google Scholar
Dyzenhaus, David. 2015. “Kelsen, Heller and Schmitt: Paradigms of Sovereignty Thought.” Theoretical Inquiries in Law 16 (2): 337–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Epp, Roger. 1991. “The Augustinian Moment in International Politics: Niebuhr, Butterfield, Wight and the Reclaiming of a Tradition.” International Politics Research Papers No. 10 Hilferding: pp. 266–71.Google Scholar
Friedrich, Carl J. and Brzezinski, Zbigniew K.. 1956. Totalitarian Dictatorship and Autocracy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Ford, Guy Stanton, ed. 1935. Dictatorship in the Modern World. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Ford, Guy Stanton. 1939. Dictatorship in the Modern World. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Fromm, Erich. 1941 [1969]. Escape from Freedom. New York: Avon Books.Google Scholar
Gartzke, Erik. 1998. “Kant We All Just Get Along? Opportunity, Willingness, and the Origins of the Democratic Peace.” American Journal of Political Science 42 (1): 127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gelpi, Christopher F., and Griesdorf, Michael. 2001. “Winners or Losers? Democracy in International Crisis, 1918–94.” American Political Science Review 95 (3): 633–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gleason, Abbott. 1995. Totalitarianism: The Inner History of the Cold War. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Guilhot, Nicolas. 2017. After the Enlightenment: Political Realism and International Relations in the Mid-20th Century. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haggard, Stephan, and Kaufman, Robert. 2021. Backsliding. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hayes, Carlton J. H. ed. 1940. “Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society.” Symposium on the Totalitarian State 82 (1): 91102.Google Scholar
Hayek, Friedrich A. 1944. The Road to Serfdom. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Herz, John H. [Eduard Bristler]. 1942. “Power Politics and World Organization.” The American Political Science Review 36 (6): 1039–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hilferding, Rudolf. 1940. “State Capitalism or Totalitarian State Economy?” The Socialist Courier, April 25. pp. 266–71. Reprinted in The Modern Review, June 1947.Google Scholar
Hitler, Adolf. 1939. “Speech in the Reichstag: January 30, 1939.” Reprinted in Baynes, Norman H. (ed.). 1942. Hitler's Speeches. London: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hoden, Marcel. 1939. “Europe without the league.” Foreign Affairs, 18 (1): 1328.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hook, Sidney. 1933. “Russia in Solution” [Review of Leon Trotsky, The History of the Russian Revolution vols. II and III], Saturday Review, 8 April.Google Scholar
Hook, Sidney. 1939. “Reflections on the Russian Revolution.” The Southern Review (Winter 1939): 429–62.Google Scholar
Hook, Sidney. 1934a. “Communism without Dogmas.” Modern Monthly, July.Google Scholar
Hook, Sidney. 1934b. “The Meaning of Marx.”Google Scholar
Hook, Sidney. 1934c. “The Democratic and Dictatorial Aspects of Communism.” International Conciliation, December.Google Scholar
Hook, Sidney. 1937. “Liberalism and the Case of Leon Trotsky.” Southern Review, Fall.Google Scholar
Hook, Sidney. 1940. “Reason, Social Myths and Democracy.”Google Scholar
Hook, Sidney. 1987. Out of Step: An Unquiet Life in the 20th Century. New York: Carroll and Graf Publishers.Google Scholar
Hoover, Calvin. 1931. The Economic Life of Soviet Russia. New York: Macmillan Company Ltd.Google Scholar
Hoover, Calvin. 1934. “Dictators and Democracies.” The Virginia Quarterly Review 10 (2): 161–76.Google Scholar
Hoover, Calvin. 1936. “The Dictators March.” The Virginia Quarterly Review 12 (3): 321–36.Google Scholar
Ikenberry, John G. 2001. After Victory: Institutions, Strategic Restraint, and the Rebuilding of Order after Major Wars. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ikenberry, John G. 2006. Liberal Order and Imperial Ambition: Essays on American Power and International Order. Boston, MA: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Inboden, William C. 2014. “The Prophetic Conflict: Reinhold Niebuhr, Christian Realism and World War II.” Journal of Diplomatic History 38 (1): 4982.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jünger, Ernst. 1930. “Total Mobilization.” (trans. Golb and Wolin). Kriegund Krieger (Jünger, ed.). Berlin: Junker und Dinnhaupt.Google Scholar
Kahler, Miles. 1997. “Inventing International Relations: International Relations Theory after 1945.” In New Thinking in International Relations Theory, edited by Doyle, Michael W. and Ikenberry, G. John, 2053. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.Google Scholar
Kelsen, Hans. 1920. Das Problem der Souveränität und die Theorie des Völkerrechts: Beitrag zu Einer Reinen Rechtslehre [The Problem of Sovereignty and the Theory of International Law: Contribution to a Pure Theory of Law]. Tübingen: Mohr.Google Scholar
Kelsen, Hans. 1934 [2002]. Reine Rechtslehre [Introduction to the Problems of Legal Theory]. B.L. Paulson and S.L. Paulson (trans.), Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Kennan, George. 1946 [1967]. “Telegraphic Message from Moscow of February 22, 1946.” In Kennan, Memoirs 1925–1950. New York: Pantheon Books.Google Scholar
Kennan, George F. [“X”] 1947. “The Sources of Soviet Conduct.” Foreign Affairs, July 1947.Google Scholar
Kennan, George F. 1954a. Realities of American Foreign Policy. Princeton, NY: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Kennan, George. 1954b. “Totalitarianism in the Modern World.” In Totalitarianism, edited by Friedrich, Carl. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Keynes, John Maynard. 1920. The Economic Consequences of the Peace. New York: Harcourt, Brace and Howe.Google Scholar
Kohn, Hans. 1935. “Communist and Fascist Dictatorships: A Comparative Study,” 141–60.Google Scholar
Kroenig, Matthew. 2020. The Return of Great Power Rivalry: Democracy versus Autocracy from the Ancient World to the U.S. and China. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lake, David A. 1992. “Powerful Pacifists: Democratic States and War.” American Political Science Review 86 (1): 2437.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laski, Harold. 1935. The State in Theory and Practice. London: Allen and Unwin Ltd.Google Scholar
Lasswell, Harold D. 1927. “The Theory of Political Propaganda.” The American Political Science Review 21 (3): 627–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lasswell, Harold D. 1935. “The Person: Subject and Object of Propaganda.” The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science 179: 187–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lasswell, Harold D. 1941. “The Garrison State.” American Journal of Sociology 46 (4): 455–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lasswell, Harold D., and Sereno, Renzo. 1937. “Governmental and Party Leaders in Fascist Italy.” The American Political Science Review 31 (5): 914–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lederer, Emil. 1940. State of the Masses: The Threat of the Classless Society. New York: W.W. Norton & Co.Google Scholar
Lee, Stephen J. 2016. European Dictatorships: 1918–1945, 4th edition, New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Linz, Juan J. 1975 [2000]. Totalitarian and Authoritarian Regimes. Boulder, CO: Lynn Rienner Publishers, Inc.Google Scholar
Lipson, Charles. 2003. Reliable Partners: How Democracies have Made a Separate Peace. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Loewenstein, Karl. 1935a. “Autocracy versus Democracy in Contemporary Europe, I.” The American Political Science Review 29 (4): 571–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loewenstein, Karl. 1935b. “Autocracy versus Democracy in Contemporary Europe, II.” The American Political Science Review 29 (5): 755–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loriaux, Michael. 1992. “The Realists and Saint Augustine: Skepticism, Psychology, and Moral Action in International Relations Thought.” International Studies Quarterly 36 (4): 401–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ludendorff, Erich. 1935. Der Totale Krieg. Munich: Druderci Ulbert Ebner.Google Scholar
Lührmann, Anna, Tannenberg, Marcus, and Lindberg, Staffan I.. 2018. “Regimes of the World (RoW): Opening New Avenues for the Comparative Study of Political Regimes.” Politics and Governance 6 (1): 6077.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miłosz, Czesław. 1953. The Captive Mind (trans. Zielonko). London: Secker & Warburg.Google Scholar
Miller, David Hunter. 1969. The Drafting of the Covenant, Volume I. New York: Putnam.Google Scholar
Marcuse, Herbert. 1934. “The Struggle against Liberalism in the Totalitarian View of the State.” In Negations, edited by Marcuse, Herbert. London: Penguin Press (reprinted in 1968).Google Scholar
Mearsheimer, John M. 1994. The Great Delusion: Liberal Dreams and International Realities. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Merkley, Paul. 1975. Reinhold Niebuhr: A Political Account. Montreal: McGill-Queen's University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morgenthau, Hans J. 1939. “International Affairs: The Resurrection of Neutrality in Europe.” The American Political Science Review 33 (3): 473–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morgenthau, Hans J. 1945. “The Evil of Politics and the Ethics of Evil.” Ethics 56 (1): 118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morgenthau, Hans J. 1962. “The Influence of Reinhold Niebuhr in American Political Life and Thought.” In Reinhold Niebuhr: A Prophetic Voice for Our Time, edited by Landen, Harold. Greenwich: Seabury Press.Google Scholar
Neumann, Franz. 1942. Behemoth: The Structure and Practice of National Socialism. New York: Oxford University Press, Revised edition 1944.Google Scholar
Neumann, Sigmund. 1935. “Germany: Battlefield of the Middle Classes.” Foreign Affairs 13 (2): 271–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neumann, Sigmund. 1938. “The Rule of the Demagogue.” American Sociological Review 3 (4): 487–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neumann, Sigmund. 1942. Permanent Revolution: Totalitarianism in the Age of International Civil War. New York: Praeger.Google Scholar
Niebuhr, Reinhold. 1932. “Moral Man and Immoral Society.” In Reinhold Niebuhr: Major Works on Religion and Politics, edited by Sifton, Elisabeth. New York: Penguin Random House [2015].Google Scholar
Niebuhr, Reinhold. 1933. “Why German Socialism Crashed.” Christian Century, 5 April.Google Scholar
Niebuhr, Reinhold. 1934. “The Churches in Germany.” The American Scholar 3, 3 (Summer): 344–51.Google Scholar
Niebuhr, Reinhold. 1938. “The Will of God and the Van Zeeland Report.” Christian Century, 55 (14 December 1938).Google Scholar
Niebuhr, Reinhold. 1940. Christianity and Power Politics. New York: Scribner and Sons [1952].Google Scholar
Niebuhr, Reinhold. 1941. The Nature and Destiny of Man: A Christian Interpretation. Louisville: Westminster John Knox Press [1996, 2015].Google Scholar
Niebuhr, Reinhold. 1944. “The Children of Light and the Children of Darkness.” In Reinhold Niebuhr: Major Works on Religion and Politics, edited by Sifton, Elisabeth. New York: Penguin Random House [2015].Google Scholar
Ortega y Gassett, José. 1930. The Revolt of the Masses (trans. Anonymous, 1932). Woking, UK: Unwin Brothers, Ltd.Google Scholar
Orwell, George. 1938. “Review of Russia under Soviet Rule by N. de Basily.” In An Age Like This: 1920–1940, edited by Sonia Orwell, and Ian Angus, . New York: Harcourt, Brace & World, Inc.Google Scholar
Orwell, George. 1949. Nineteen Eighty-Four. London: Secker & Warburg.Google Scholar
Osiander, Andreas. 2012. “Rereading Early Twentieth-Century IR Theory: Idealism Revisited.” In International Relations and the First Great Debate (2012), edited by Schmidt, Brian C., pp. 39–59. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Owen, John M. 1995. “How Liberalism Produces Democratic Peace.” International Security 19 (2): 87125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peceny, Mark, Beer, Caroline C. and Sanchez-Terry, Shannon. 2002. “Dictatorial Peace?American Political Science Review, 96 (1): 1526.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peceny, Mark and Butler, Christopher K., 2004. “The Conflict Behavior of Authoritarian Regimes.” International Politics, 41: 565–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Phelps, Christopher. 1997. Young Sidney Hook: Marxist and Pragmatist. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Pollock, Friedrich. 1941. “State Capitalism: Its Possibilities and Limitations.” In The Essential Frankfurt School Reader, edited by Andrew Arato, and Eike Gebhardt, . Oxford: Basil Blackwell (Reprinted 1978).Google Scholar
Preuss, Lawrence. 1935. “National Socialist Conceptions of International Law.” The American Political Science Review, 29 (4): 594609.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quigley, Harold S. 1939. “Dictatorship in the Far East.” In Dictatorship in the Modern World, edited by Ford, Guy Stanton. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Quirk, Joel and Vigneswaran, Darshan. 2005. “The Construction of an Edifice: The Story of a First Great Debate.” Review of International Studies 31 (1): 89107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rahv, Philip. 1938. “Trials of the Mind.” Partisan Review, 4, 5 April 1938, 3–11).Google Scholar
Reiter, Dan. 2017. “Is Democracy a Cause of Peace?” Oxford Research Encyclopedias.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rengger, Nicholas, and Thirkell-White, Ben, eds. 2017. Critical International Relations Theory after 25 Years. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rich, Paul. 1992. “Reinhold Niebuhr and the Ethics of Realism in International Relations.” History of Political Thought 13 (2): 281–98.Google Scholar
Rocco, Alfredo. 1925. “The Political Doctrine of Fascism.” trans. D. Bigongiari (International Conciliation, no. 223, Carnegie Endowment for International Peace, 1926).Google Scholar
Russett, Bruce. 1993. Grasping the Democratic Peace: Principles for a Post-Cold War World. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Service, Robert. 2009. Trotsky: A Biography. Boston: Belknap Press.Google Scholar
Shapiro, Scott J. and Hathaway, Oona A.. 2017. The Internationalists: How a Radical Plan to Outlaw War Remade the World. New York: Simon and Schuster.Google Scholar
Schmitt, Carl. 1985 [1922]. Political Theology. The University of Chicago Press. Originally published as Politische Theologie: Vier Kapitel zur Lehre von der Souveranitat 1922, revised edition 1934, Berlin: Duncker Humblot.Google Scholar
Schmitt, Carl. 1993 [1929]. “The Age of Neutralizations and Depoliticizations” (trans. Konzett and McCormick). Telos 26 (2): 130–42. Originally published as “Das Zeitalter der Neutralisierungen und Entpolitisierungen,” 1929.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schmidt, Brian C. 1998. The Political Discourse of Anarchy: A Disciplinary History of International Relations. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Schmidt, Brian C. ed. 2012. International Relations and the First Great Debate (2012). New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Schultz, Kenneth A. 1998. “Domestic Opposition and Signaling in International Crises.” American Political Science Review 92 (4): 829–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schultz, Kenneth A. 2009. Democracy and Coercive Diplomacy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Siverson, Randolph M. 1995. “Democracies and War Participation: In Defense of the Institutional Constraints Argument.” European Journal of International Relations 1 (4): 481–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stein, Guenther. 1938. “‘Totalitarian’ Japan.” Foreign Affairs 16 (2): 294308.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steiner, H. Arthur. 1936. “The Fascist Conception of Law.” Columbia Law Review 36 (8): 1267–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thies, Cameron G. 2002. “Progress, History and Identity in International Relations Theory: The Case of the Idealist-Realist Debate.” European Journal of International Relations 8 (2): 147–85.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thompson, Dorothy. 1935. “National Socialism: Theory and Practice.” Foreign Affairs 13 (4): 557–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thompson, Kenneth. 2009. “Niebuhr and the Foreign Policy Realists.” In Reinhold Niebuhr Revisited: Engagements with an American Original, edited by Rice, Daniel. Grand Rapids, MI. pp. 139–160. Michigan: Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing Co.Google Scholar
Tillich, Paul. 1934. “The Totalitarian State and the Claims of the Church.” Social Research 1: 4, reprinted in Social Research 82, 1 (Spring: 49–77).Google Scholar
Trotsky, Leon. 1934. War and the Fourth International. Trotsky Internet Archive at https://www.marxists.org/archive/trotsky/1934/06/warfi.htm.Google Scholar
Trotsky, Leon. 1937. The Revolution Betrayed: What is the Soviet Union and Where is it Going? New York: Pathfinder Press.Google Scholar
Voegelin, Eric. 1938. “The Political Religions.” In Modernity Without Restraint: Volume 5 in the Collected Works of Eric Voegelin, Sandoz, Ellis (ed.) Columbia, MO: University of Missouri Press (reprinted in 2000).Google Scholar
Wald, Alan W. 1987. The New York Intellectuals: The Rise and Decline of the Anti-Stalinist Left from the 1930s to the 1980s. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press.Google Scholar
Waltz, Kenneth N. 1967. Foreign Policy and Democratic Politics: The American and British Experience. Boston: Little, Brown and Co.Google Scholar
Warren, Heather A. 1997. Theologians of a New World Order: Reinhold Niebuhr and the Christian Realists. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weeks, Jessica L. P. 2014. “Dictators at War and Peace.” Ithaca NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Weeks, Jessica. 2008. “Autocratic Audience Costs: Regime Type and Signaling Resolve.” International Organization 62: 3564.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weeks, Jessica. 2012. “Strongmen and Straw Men: Authoritarian Regimes and the Initiation of International Conflict.” American Political Science Review 106 (2): 326–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Westbrook, Robert. 1991. John Dewey and American Democracy. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Wilson, Peter. 1998. “The Myth of the ‘First Great Debate’.” Review of International Studies 24: 115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar