Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-gtxcr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-23T12:41:34.286Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

It is not enough to sing its praises: the very foundations of precision psychiatry may be scientifically unsound and require examination

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  09 February 2021

Jim van Os*
Affiliation:
Department of Psychiatry, UMC Utrecht Brain Centre, University Medical Centre Utrecht, Utrecht University, Utrecht, The Netherlands Department of Psychiatry and Neuropsychology, School for Mental Health and Neuroscience, Maastricht University Medical Centre, Maastricht, The Netherlands Department of Psychosis Studies, Institute of Psychiatry, Psychology & Neuroscience, King's College London, London, UK
Annemarie C. J. Kohne
Affiliation:
Department of Psychiatry, UMC Utrecht Brain Centre, University Medical Centre Utrecht, Utrecht University, Utrecht, The Netherlands Department of Psychiatry, Academic Medical Centre in Amsterdam, Amsterdam, The Netherlands
*
Author for correspondence: Jim van Os, E-mail: j.j.vanos-2@umcutrecht.nl
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Invited Letter Rejoinder
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted re- use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2021. Published by Cambridge University Press

Reply to Salagre and Vieta

We thank Salagre and Vieta for their thoughtful and cogent comments. The admission that they are ‘in love’ with the concept of precision psychiatry, while in jest, does hit the nail on the head as it may be best summarized as exactly that: a collective overvalued belief that ‘biology plays a determinant role’ and that ‘mental disorders are disorders of the brain’ to be ‘tracked through biological clues’. In their reply, they reiterate the promise of precision psychiatry: how multi-omics, neuroimaging, big data and a range of high-density data approaches should converge towards specific biomarkers that can lead to biological stratification and, ultimately, to ‘precise’, person-specific treatments. They suggest that the types of fundamental concerns that we raise are best relegated to the realm of psychology. What is implied – without quite stating it – is that mental disorders (mental states) are expressions of brain pathology (physical states) and therefore should be studied under a linear model of body/brain-causes-mind. The issue of understanding possible ‘biomarkers’ of human emotions (as they frame our concern that it remains unknown if, how and to what degree mental phenomena are represented physically and – even if this were so – why this would be relevant to understanding mental suffering) is another concern altogether that they suggest takes us into ‘philosophical grounds’ which remain outside the scope of precision psychiatry.

Is precision psychiatry self-evident?

We believe their reply is important as it forms part of what Braslow and colleagues refer to as ‘psychiatry's taken-for-granted, everyday beliefs’: that the promise of precise biology to remedy mental suffering is enough to make it self-evident (Braslow, Brekke, & Levenson, Reference Braslow, Brekke and Levenson2020). The implicit premise of precision psychiatry is that phenomena of the mind are physically represented and that these representations are relevant to our understanding of mental suffering. This belief is so strong that it does not require explicit reflection, let alone further examination. To belong to the traditional academic psychiatric community is to reiterate the self-evident nature of the belief. To seriously entertain the hypothesis that, for example, schizophrenia may not be a self-evident disorder of the brain is dismissed as ‘antipsychiatry’ (Sommer, Kahn, Denys, Schoevers, & Aleman, Reference Sommer, Kahn, Denys, Schoevers and Aleman2015).

However, not everybody agrees with such a stance. In fact, psychiatry is faced with increasingly blunt assessments of its reductionist belief system, written by eminent – mostly non-psychiatric – scholars in prestigious mainstream journals (some examples in Table 1). Since the civil rights movements of reformist psychiatry in the 1970s (later framed as ‘antipsychiatry’) and the ‘recovery movement’ in the 1980s, the patient's voice, and the focus on the existential domain of personal recovery, has not gained much traction in academic psychiatry, some even considering it a ‘hoax’ (Schizophrenia Research Forum, 28 November 2017). As a result, recovery-focussed work in the mental health care sector is hampered by limited ‘institutional readiness’ (Leamy et al., Reference Leamy, Clarke, Le Boutillier, Bird, Janosik, Sabas and Slade2014) and by psychiatry's inability and/or unwillingness to escape the ‘epistemic prison’ of the ‘right medication for the right DSM-diagnosis’ (Gardner & Kleinman, Reference Gardner and Kleinman2019; Hyman, Reference Hyman2010). In reaction, novel and increasingly popular movements like Mad in America (MIA; www.madinamerica.com) produce a stream of articles focussed on debunking the same belief system that Salagre and Vieta passionately advocate. Although it is easy to dismiss MIA as unreasonable ‘antipsychiatry’ (Sommer et al., Reference Sommer, Kahn, Denys, Schoevers and Aleman2015), it may also be viewed as a campaign to address epistemic injustice (Crichton, Carel, & Kidd, Reference Crichton, Carel and Kidd2017) brought about by the ‘myopia’ (Braslow et al., Reference Braslow, Brekke and Levenson2020) of an academic psychiatry that has unlearned to hear an individual's personal meaning in the experience of mental distress.

Table 1. Recent publications about how ‘precision psychiatry’ is viewed outside psychiatry

AI solutionism

Apart from raising the model of pathological-brain/body-causes-abnormal-mind to the level of self-evidence, ignoring the ‘hard problem of consciousness', Salagre and Vieta assume another self-evident property of mental suffering: that it is determinable and predictable. Thus, they assume that there naturally will be such a thing as the ‘right treatment’ at the ‘right dose’ at the ‘right time’ for an individual with mental distress. In their view, analytical innovations such as machine learning will unravel determinability and predictability for use in clinical practice. However, this stance overlooks the underlying question to what degree mental suffering can be considered determinable and predictable in the first place – and therefore runs the risk of becoming a form of messaging called ‘AI solutionism’ (AI = artificial intelligence). This is the supposition that, as long as there is enough data, any human outcome can be computed based on machine learning algorithms (Chen & Asch, Reference Chen and Asch2017). The question, however, is whether this can be considered a reasonable hypothesis in the case of mental outcomes.

AI solutionism holds that mental outcomes are determined – and therefore predictable. However, mental outcomes are unpredictable because they are inextricably linked to stochastic events in a complex system where chaos theory rules. Chaos theory describes the phenomenon that with the wisdom of hindsight all events may well be determined – but prospectively remain unpredictable. Although there are undoubtedly factors which have a statistical association with mental outcomes – for example, the loss of a loved one and the subsequent feeling of sorrow – the moment of losing a loved one at some point in time is unpredictable.

It is attractive to assume that, say, getting better on an antidepressant is a kind of determined process so that machine learning based on ‘everything’ can predict treatment response in a particular patient. However, the scientific basis for this is lacking, both conceptually and meta-analytically (e.g. Kennis et al., Reference Kennis, Gerritsen, van Dalen, Williams, Cuijpers and Bockting2020). The reason for this was described by Tikhodeyev and Shcherbakova in the context of the mutagenic effect of ultraviolet radiation. Although the amount of mutagenic damage in microorganisms can be reliably predicted based on the amount of radiation, temperature, duration and culture medium, it cannot be predicted in which microorganism and where, in this microorganism, in the genome mutations will occur (Tikhodeyev & Shcherbakova, Reference Tikhodeyev and Shcherbakova2019). The explanation, according to chaos theory, is that even in the case of a deterministic (non-random) process, simple nonlinear systems cannot be predicted in the future. Machine learning cannot solve this (Chen & Asch, Reference Chen and Asch2017).

The same applies to mental suffering: although there are weak therapeutic influences of factors at the group level, it remains unpredictable whether these influences lead to change in the stochastic ecosystem of a specific individual. Unpredictability in the ecosystem is partly due to the so-called butterfly effect: the sensitivity of the future to the most minute random change in the baseline condition. The importance of the butterfly effect is all the greater when one understands that ‘getting better’ on an antidepressant is largely dependent on a complex placebo-effect that has to do with expectation, relationship, being observed and time (Kirsch, Reference Kirsch2014). Therefore, we fail to see why determinability and predictability should be considered self-evident postulates of precision psychiatry.

Conclusion

In conclusion, the very foundations of the concept of precision psychiatry are unsafe. It is therefore not enough to merely sing its praises. Perhaps it would be more prudent to first focus on the scientific holes in the theory before building a practice that the world outside the culture of traditional academic psychiatry is increasingly unwilling to accept.

References

Braslow, J. T., Brekke, J. S., & Levenson, J. (2020). Psychiatry's myopia-reclaiming the social, cultural, and psychological in the psychiatric gaze. JAMA Psychiatry. doi: 10.1001/jamapsychiatry.2020.2722Google ScholarPubMed
Chen, J. H., & Asch, S. M. (2017). Machine learning and prediction in medicine – Beyond the peak of inflated expectations. New England Journal of Medicine, 376, 25072509. doi: 10.1056/NEJMp1702071CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crichton, P., Carel, H., & Kidd, I. J. (2017). Epistemic injustice in psychiatry. British Journal of Psychiatry Bulletin, 41, 6570. doi: 10.1192/pb.bp.115.050682Google Scholar
Dumas-Mallet, E., & Gonon, F. (2020) Messaging in biological psychiatry: Misrepresentations, their causes, and potential consequences. Harvard Review of Psychiatry, 28, 395403.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gardner, C., & Kleinman, A. (2019). Medicine and the mind – The consequences of psychiatry's identity crisis. New England Journal of Medicine, 381, 16971699. doi: 10.1056/NEJMp1910603CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hyman, S. E. (2010). The diagnosis of mental disorders: The problem of reification. Annual Review of Clinical Psychology, 6, 155179. doi: 10.1146/annurev.clinpsy.3.022806.091532CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ioannidis, J. P. A. (2019). Therapy and prevention for mental health: What if mental diseases are mostly not brain disorders? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 42, e13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kennis, M., Gerritsen, L., van Dalen, M., Williams, A., Cuijpers, P., & Bockting, C. (2020). Prospective biomarkers of major depressive disorder: A systematic review and meta-analysis. Molecular Psychiatry, 25, 321338. doi: 10.1038/s41380-019-0585-zCrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kirsch, I. (2014). Antidepressants and the placebo effect. Zeitschrift für Psychologie, 222, 128134. doi: 10.1027/2151-2604/a000176CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Leamy, M., Clarke, E., Le Boutillier, C., Bird, V., Janosik, M., Sabas, K., … Slade, M. (2014). Implementing a complex intervention to support personal recovery: A qualitative study nested within a cluster randomised controlled trial. PLoS One, 9, e97091. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0097091CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sommer, I., Kahn, R., Denys, D., Schoevers, R., & Aleman, A. (2015). Schizofrenie als diagnose schrappen is antipsychiatrie uit de jaren 70 [To abandon the diagnosis of schizophrenia is antipsychiatry of the seventies]. NRC Handelsblad, 13 maart 2015, Opinie, p 17.Google Scholar
Tikhodeyev, O. N., & Shcherbakova, O. V. (2019). The problem of non-shared environment in behavioral genetics. Behavior Genetics, 49, 259269. doi: 10.1007/s10519-019-09950-1CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Figure 0

Table 1. Recent publications about how ‘precision psychiatry’ is viewed outside psychiatry