Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-cx56b Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-09-27T07:19:36.327Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

No Orthopathy without Orthoaesthesis: On the Necessity of Negative Effort

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  15 May 2024

Ryan Duns*
Affiliation:
Marquette University; ryan.duns@marquette.edu
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Theologians have become increasingly attentive to the role emotion and experience must play in theological reflection. Several thinkers have recently done so by appropriating and developing Jon Sobrino’s understanding of orthopathy, or “right affect.” A close examination of these efforts, however, reveals inconsistencies in the way the category is understood and deployed. This article redresses these inconsistencies by complementing orthopathy with orthoaesthesis, or “right perception.” The article opens by considering various appeals to orthopathy before suggesting how William James’s theory of emotion might provide the category with clarifying content. The second stage engages Simone Weil and Iris Murdoch as practitioners of orthoaesthesis. Special attention is given to Murdoch’s “techniques” aimed at transforming how practitioners perceive reality. With Murdoch’s guidance, the article contends that orthopathy is ineluctably bound to and not possible without orthoaesthesis. The article concludes with a constructive proposal to show how orthoaesthesis-orthopathy contributes to a Christian theological anthropology.

Type
Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the President and Fellows of Harvard College

Introduction

In recent decades, theologians have shown an increased interest in the role emotion and affective experience must play in theological reflection. Footnote 1 Especially among thinkers influenced by Jon Sobrino, the category of orthopathy, or “right affect,” has been used to give due attention to the way emotion and experience act as theological loci. Yet a close reading of these thinkers uncovers inconsistencies in how orthopathy is construed. This is so because Sobrino never elaborates orthopathy’s content. Ironically, his account of “right affection” neglects to offer any account of the emotions. This article attempts to address this lacuna. First, it begins with an overview of orthopathy and considers ways it has been used. Because the category lacks a consistent understanding of the emotions, the article revisits William James’s pioneering, if often misinterpreted, “What is an Emotion?” Reading James in light of recent work in neuroscience, we find that he furnishes a surprisingly contemporary account of what emotions are and how a theory of the emotions can contribute to orthopathy. This leads to the second, constructive, phase. For James, emotions are psychophysical responses that reflect one’s experience and interpretation of the world. Thus, how one perceives shapes how one is affected. This leads me to propose that orthopathy must be complemented with orthoaesthesis, or “right perception,” hence the title: “no orthoaesthesis without orthopathy.” To lay the groundwork for an account of orthoaesthesis, I draw on Simone Weil and Iris Murdoch and discuss how practices of “negative effort” can refine one’s perception. Informed and, through practices of negative effort, formed by their philosophy, we discover the relationship between orthoaesthesis and orthopathy. I conclude with a brief suggestion for how the orthoaesthesis-orthopathy dialectic might contribute to a more comprehensive Christian theological anthropology.

Orthopathy: Three Genealogies, Five Uses

It may surprise readers, especially Catholic theologians, that the neologism “orthopathy” originates not with Jon Sobrino but with Theodore Runyon (1930–2017). Footnote 2 Runyon recognized the challenge that appealing to the category of “religious experience” poses to theological reflection, for when appealing to religious experience, what prevents one from sliding into subjectivism? Footnote 3

Inspired by John Wesley, Runyon sought a mode of theological reflection that took appeals to religious experience seriously. “The knowledge of God,” Runyon writes, “is not just believing the right things (orthodoxy), or doing the right things (orthopraxy), but involves the experience of the reality of God that is the product, not of the subjective imagination, but of the divine Spirit.” Footnote 4 Theology requires more than assenting or doing. It involves being affected by and transformed through an encounter with God’s grace. So, Runyon asks, “Just as orthodoxy sets guidelines and standards for right doctrine, and orthopraxy sets standards for right practices, is there a need for an ‘orthopathy’ (right feelings, affections, and in the larger sense experience) that can offer norms and guidelines for right religious experience?” Footnote 5

Runyon answers this question by proposing six criteria. Orthopathic experience 1) must transcend subjectivism by giving priority to the world external to the self, 2) be transformative, 3) recognize the social and shared character of experience, 4) be rational, 5) be sacramental, and 6) be teleological. Footnote 6 Orthopathy, for Runyon, “makes its contribution to ecumenical theology by adding the religious experience dimension to orthodoxy and orthopraxy. It puts orthodoxy in the context of a living faith relation, and orthopraxy in the context of a synergy in which the Holy Spirit is the co-producer of our activity.” Footnote 7 With his category and evaluative criteria, Runyon found a way for theologians to attend to religious experience and the affections within an integrated vision of theological anthropology. At no point, however, does he directly address the nature of the emotions or the role they play in religious experience. Moreover, despite authoring the neologism, Runyon’s influence seems limited to Wesleyan and Pentecostal circles. None of the authors considered below attribute their use of orthopathy to Runyon but to Jon Sobrino. Footnote 8

With Sobrino’s La fe en Jesucristo: Ensayo desde las victimas, orthopathy was introduced to a wide theological audience. Footnote 9 The gospel, for Sobrino, is “Good News” in three ways. First, what Jesus announces and enacts—the kingdom of God—is orthopraxis. Second, what Jesus accomplishes through his death and resurrection—the kerygma—is assented to in faith as orthodoxy. Third (yet too often neglected), Jesus’s “manner of being in his service to the Kingdom of God, and in his relationship to the Father” is also good news. Footnote 10 In Jesus, believers encounter and confess the one who reveals the “good news of what is truly human.” Footnote 11 As Sobrino uses it, orthopathy describes “the correct way of letting ourselves be affected by the reality of Christ.” Footnote 12 Because encounter with Jesus is at once cognitive and affective, believers cannot content themselves with theorizing about Jesus but must consider how Jesus’s way of being, “his closeness, honesty, tenderness toward the weak,” Footnote 13 must guide the transformation of their lives. The question of orthopathy is not limited to a cognitive “What do you know about Christ?” but interrogates, at an existential level, “How has knowing Christ affected your heart and reformed your life?” How does undergoing an encounter with Christ form and transform how one interacts with the world? How is the disciple’s life different for having been correctly touched by a graced encounter?

Now, it must be said that Sobrino does not envision the orthopathic response as requiring one to slavishly reenact Jesus’s life. He maintains, instead, that those whose hearts have been affected by an encounter with Christ will live a life that bears a “fundamental isomorphism” with Jesus’s. Footnote 14 Orthopathy addresses the way conversion, or metanoia, inspires disciples to adopt Jesus’s disposition toward others. Whereas orthodoxy describes what one believes and orthopraxis what one does, orthopathy speaks to how one’s being affected by Christ flows into and manifests itself in Christianity’s “right belief” and “right action.” Nevertheless, like Runyon, Sobrino neglects to account for the role the emotions play within orthopathy. This lacuna is also present in authors who have recently sought to appropriate and apply Sobrino’s category to contemporary issues. The reason for engaging Annie Selak, Glen Butner, and Edward Vacek below is that they provide three attempts to theologically explicate and apply the concept of orthopathy. What binds them, in addition to their stated intent, is a common neglect to provide an account of what emotions are or how they contribute to orthopathy.

Annie Selak directly engages Sobrino’s understanding of orthodoxy, orthopraxis, and orthopathy to evaluate recent contributions to the feminist kenosis debate. Footnote 15 At issue is the way theologians have used the idea of kenosis, or self-emptying, to oppress women. Such misuses reflect a sinister and often patriarchal logic: Jesus suffered and died on the Cross; can you expect any less? Be like Christ and do not refuse your cup: abuse, oppression, neglect. Take courage and, inspired by Jesus’s self-emptying, drink the cup’s bitter gall. Such a summons to self-abasement must be negated. Thus, and rightly, Selak assays to articulate an understanding of kenosis that has been purged of its potentially abusive ballast. Rightly repristinated, Selak envisions kenosis as becoming “a vital component of feminist spirituality.” Footnote 16

Selak rightly insists that an orthopathically developed theology will look to the emotional impact theology has on women. Ideas and practices that empower women are to be lifted up and celebrated; practices that denigrate or diminish women must be abandoned. Footnote 17 Yet Selak never advances beyond Sobrino’s description of orthopathy as the correct way of being affected by Christ, nor does she offer a developed account of the way orthopathy can be used to address and assess the emotional impact of theology on women’s beliefs and practices. Ironically, in an essay intended to argue for the importance of orthopathy, no substantive account of the emotions is offered. Although Selak justifiably wants a space within theology for the emotions, her reliance on Sobrino’s definition impedes this effort because Sobrino does not offer a fleshed-out account of the emotions. While Selak’s essay records a necessary intervention signaling the need for theologians to pay heed to the role emotions play in theological reflection and in the life of faith, more work remains to be done.

Glenn Butner offers a second approach. Judging Sobrino’s categories, especially orthopathy, as essential for stimulating conversation between theologians and economists, Butner, like Selak, accepts Sobrino’s basic definition of orthopathy but extends it in a new way:

Orthopathy indicates a broad and fundamental orientation toward God and the world. This fundamental orientation is neither consciously cognitional, as toward specific doctrines or historical truth-claims, nor is it dynamic, as fulfilled in the doing of certain actions. It does not consist of propositional ideas or concrete actions. Rather, orthopathy requires one to adopt a pre-reflective or pre-intentional orientation toward the world, an orientation that allows a person to complete acts in a particular manner. Footnote 18

Butner rightly distinguishes orthopathy from orthodoxy (abstract, cognitional) and orthopraxis (concrete, dynamic), but like Selak and Sobrino, he neglects to offer an account of the emotions. As a result, his use of orthopathy lacks conceptual clarity. Indeed, Butner’s description of orthopathy is surprisingly abstract and cognitional. Can one intentionally “adopt a pre-reflective” orientation? A little later, he describes orthopathy as “pre-reflective or pre-intentional,” yet this seems hard to square with Sobrino’s definition. Footnote 19 If orthopathy is the right way of being affected by Christ, and if orthopathy animates orthodoxy and orthopraxis, can one legitimately relegate it to a pre-intentional status? Although he attributes his use of orthopathy to Sobrino, Butner’s description seems more indebted to Charles Taylor’s “social imaginary.” Footnote 20 Regardless, Butner’s justified insistence on foregrounding the importance of the affections glaringly omits any direct discussion of the affections. Sobrino’s silence on this topic, it seems, enshrouds those who borrow from him.

A third take on orthopathy comes from Edward Vacek. Footnote 21 Vacek’s treatment advances beyond those of Sobrino, Selak, and Butner, as he does provide a more developed and nuanced account of the affections and their importance to theological reflection. He directs attention to the way “our affections ground and give significance to our intellectual and volitional activity” Footnote 22 and insists that any theology that disregards the emotions cannot be adequate. What makes Vacek’s essay hard to position is that he claims orthopathy as his neologism: “As is obvious, I am inventing a new word.” Footnote 23

Of interest here is Vacek’s engagement with philosophical, sociological, and psychological research. These sources permit him to construct a larger framework for reflecting theologically on the emotions. His concern is the way emotions contribute to, or derogate from, an embrace of orthodoxy. Emotions, Vacek observes, reveal values. Citing the Catechism of the Catholic Church (§1771), he agrees that they are the way one “intuits the good and suspects evil.” Footnote 24 Emotions are neither “locked inside my head” nor reducible to bodily perturbations but are, instead, cognitive evaluations of a world encountered as value-saturated: “the corollary is that without our emotions, we would not experience the world as valuable.” Footnote 25 For Vacek, we do not interact with a world that is neutrally there but comport ourselves within a world charged with value. Emotions forge connections between us and the world. We are affected by what is other to us; we move toward or away from what we evaluate as good or evil. These movements establish ties between us and the world. Love, Paul wrote to the Corinthians, transforms how we perceive; without love, knowledge about the mysteries of God is meaningless (1 Cor 13:2). Vacek, unconsciously aligning with Runyon and Sobrino, recognizes, that to be credible, orthodoxy and orthopraxis must be rooted in a love-quickened or orthopathic heart. Nevertheless, Vacek, too, leaves underdeveloped his account of just what emotions are.

Orthopathy: one category with three distinct genealogies. Although all five theologians insist on incorporating the affections into theological reflection, none of them develops an account of what emotions are or how they serve as bearers of cognitive content. To fill in these gaps, I propose returning to the work of American psychologist William James. James provided an early, influential, and, as we shall see, much misunderstood account of the emotions. Recent efforts by several psychologists and neuroscientists have, however, begun to vindicate James’s original insights into the emotions. Footnote 26 William James understood the intimate relationship between perception and affection or, closer to our terms, between aesthesis and pathos. Although other theorists of emotion could be engaged, I focus on James because his works, with some finesse, highlight the relationship between perception and affection. James not only contributes content to our understanding of orthopathy, but he also builds a bridge to our discussion of orthoaesthesis.

William James on Emotion

William James’s 1884 “What Is an Emotion?” attempted to overthrow a dominant view of emotions and replace it with his own. He sets up the contrasting viewpoints:

Our natural way of thinking about these standard emotions [surprise, curiosity, fear, anger, lust, etc.] is that the mental perception of some fact excited the mental affection called the emotion, and that this latter state of mind gives rise to the bodily expression. My thesis on the contrary is that the bodily changes follow directly the PERCEPTION of the exciting fact, and that our feeling of the same changes as they occur IS the emotion. Footnote 27

We commonly think of emotions as mental events. One experiences a stimulus, evaluates it, and the resulting judgment produces an emotion that leads to bodily changes. Emotions, in this account, eventuate in bodily action. To schematize the sequence: Perception (Monster Under Bed) ◊ Emotion (Fear) ◊ Bodily Response (Heart Rate) ◊ Action. James contests this order. He believed that the body’s physical responses play an essential role in the constitution of emotions. And most of us who have been taught James’s theory, or the so-called James-Lange theory of emotions, found it rendered in this manner: Perception (Monster Under Bed) ◊ Bodily Response (Heart Rate) ◊ Emotion (Fear). Psychologist Phoebe Ellsworth, however, contests this schematization because it oversimplifies James’s point. James did not believe that emotions are nothing more than the experience of bodily changes. This schema ignores how, for James, “the sense of the bodily changes provides the emotionality to what would otherwise be a neutral perception or interpretation of the situation. Bodily experiences are not the whole experience; they are the part that makes the whole experience emotional.” Footnote 28 James understood well the psychophysical nature of emotions and the way perception and emotion intermediate with one another. In what follows, I will draw on Ellsworth and Lisa Feldman Barrett to propose a third schema for understanding the emotions. James, I suggest, offers a much more sophisticated and illuminating account of the emotions than we have been led to believe.

Let us revisit James’s distinction between the commonsense view and his. Common sense, he writes, says:

We lose our fortune, are sorry and weep; we meet a bear, are frightened, and run; we are insulted by a rival, are angry, and strike. The hypothesis here to be defended says that this order of sequence is incorrect, that the one mental state is not immediately induced by the other, that the bodily manifestations must first be interposed between, and the more rational statement is that we feel sorry because we cry, angry because we strike, afraid because we tremble, and not that we cry, strike, or tremble, because we are sorry, angry, or fearful, as the case may be. Footnote 29

James rejects the common sense sequence (perception à emotion à bodily response) because he cannot envision a “purely disembodied emotion.” Footnote 30 For James, as for Destutt de Tracy (1754–1836), there can be no experience of emotion without some change in bodily sensation. Footnote 31 In the wake of his wife’s death, C. S. Lewis captures vividly the body’s role in experiencing emotion: “No one ever told me that grief felt so like fear. I am not afraid, but the sensation is like being afraid. The same fluttering in the stomach, the same restlessness, the yawning. I keep on swallowing.” Footnote 32 The body is not, for James, passively interposed between perception and emotion but actively contributes to how one is affected by and emotionally responds to what one perceives.

James’s insight into the body’s contribution to the emotions never gained traction. W. L. Worcester lampoons James by seizing on the bear:

A chained or caged bear may excite only feelings of curiosity, and a well armed hunter might experience only pleasurable feelings at meeting one loose in the woods. It is not, then, the perception of the bear that excites the movement of fear. We do not run from the bear unless we suppose him capable of doing us bodily injury. Why should the expectation of being eaten, for instance, set the muscles of our legs in motion? “Common sense” would be likely to say that it was because we object to being eaten; but according to Professor James the reason we dislike to be eaten is because we run away.Footnote 33

Worcester, Ellsworth argues, oversimplifies James’s account. Were Worcester correct in his portrayal, James would be a proto-behaviorist whose account of the emotions would amount to little more than a stimulus-response model. Worcester believes that, for James, any perception of a bear must necessarily result in the emotion of fear. See the bear, feel fear. Of course, as Worcester’s counterexample demonstrates, this is patently absurd: surely, there is no “universal” response to the “bear” because the context in which the bear is perceived shapes how one responds. Thus, what we commonly regard as the James-Lange theory of emotion (Perception ◊ Bodily Response ◊ Emotion) is indeed incredible and untenable.

As Ellsworth observes, scholars have generally accepted Worcester’s portrayal of James’s position, despite James’s own efforts to clarify his position in a subsequent essay. Footnote 34 Citing James’s own examples—losing a fortune and being insulted—she pushes back against conventional portrayals of James’s theory. For James, emotions are not bereft of cognitive content. The Dow Jones plummeting or a colleague’s insult elicits an affective response because each is cognitively interpreted. As the Dow plummets, my physical weeping manifests sorrow that my fortune has evaporated; looking at my smug colleague, making my hand into a fist, and getting “hot under the collar” manifests anger. Thus, Ellsworth observes, “there is no question that when James used the term perception, he meant more than simple sensation; he meant cognitive appraisal.” Footnote 35 Emotions are not passively provoked but rather produced through a combination of physical and cognitive responses to one’s world. James’s account of the emotions, I argue, is thicker and more nuanced than that found in textbooks.

In 1894, James attempted to respond to critics, but it was too little, too late. In “The Physical Basis of Emotion,” he explicitly foregrounds the role of context and cognitive interpretation: “Objects are certainly the primitive arousers of instinctive reflex movement. But they take their place, as experience goes on, as elements in total ‘situations,’ the other suggestions of which may prompt to movements of an entirely different sort.” Footnote 36 We are not, on this account, passive slaves to instinct. Nor, for that matter, should we expect the same stimulus to evoke identical responses either from the same person or across a range of persons (as though emotions were universally preprogrammed responses to stimuli). Why? Because each person’s emotions reflect a unique synthesis of physiological and cognitive inputs. What one perceives cannot but be shaped by one’s experiences and expectations. Every sensory manifold—an object’s size, shape, sound, color, distance, attributes—is bodily perceived and cognitively evaluated. No percept—whether bear or insult or falling stock—moves straight into the nervous system (stimulus-response) but must pass through an interpretive schema. Emotional responses, Lisa Feldman Barrett observes, are the “brain’s creation of what your bodily sensations mean, in relation to what is going on around you in the world.” Footnote 37 Emotions are an embodied judgment that reflects the way the subject’s perceptions are conditioned 1) within one’s total context, 2) in light of one’s past experiences, 3) with an orientation to future action, that 4) reflects the agent’s cognitive appraisal of and readiness to respond to the situation. An example: there is no contextless “caress” of the cheek. In the arms of my beloved, I submit to the loving touch. The same gentle stroke, on a crowded bus filled with strangers, elicits from me a significantly different appraisal and an energetic response to flee. Whether amorousness or terror, each emotion registers the meaning of a perception contextually received and cognitively appraised.

Barrett argues that what is taught as the James-Lange theory is, in fact, the creation of John Dewey. Footnote 38 Ironically, James’s effort to counteract behaviorist or “essentialist” understandings of the emotion was subverted by Dewey, thereby attributing to him a theory he did not hold. But James did not think there was a universal “essence” or “biological fingerprint” for fear or anger or joy. James believed “each instance of emotion, not each category of emotion, comes from a unique bodily state…. It means you can tremble in fear, jump in fear, freeze in fear, scream in fear, gasp in fear, hide in fear, attack in fear, and even laugh in the face of fear. Each occurrence of fear is associated with a different set of internal changes or sensations.” Footnote 39 Fear, like all emotions, is context-dependent and its tonalities and expressions reflect the perceiver’s past experiences and present cognitive appraisal of the situation; these past experiences and present appraisals incline the subject toward future action. Moreover, there is not a univocal or universal emotion known as “fear.” As James observed, one must learn to discern “how almost infinitely numerous and subtle” the emotions may be. Footnote 40 One learns to discern the flow of and variations within emotions, Barret writes, by acquiring and becoming increasingly fluent in using emotional concepts. Footnote 41 We grow as discerners of emotion—others’ as well as our own—by experiencing, reflecting, and learning to detect “functional resemblances” or analogies with other subjects’ experiences. Footnote 42

Before suggesting James’s contributions to orthopathy, allow me to posit a third schematization of his theory that shows the relationship between aesthesis and pathos:

Figure 1.

Emotions arise within and reflect the subject’s total situation. Physical perception (through the senses) and cognitive appraisal (interpretation) intermediate and are synthesized as the emotion. The emotion is not “just a feeling” but is a whole-body judgment that is informed by experience and prepares one for action. Nor is this unidirectional: emotions feed back into and contour how we perceive and interpret other sensations. What and how we feel colors and influences what and how we perceive our world. Thus, the task of growing as “feelers” requires one to learn to discern, with ever finer distinctions, how well or poorly we understand our emotions and the emotions of others.

First published in 1946 as “Essai sur la notion de lecture,” Simone Weil’s “Essay on the Notion of Reading” aligns with James’s understanding of the emotions. The world, for Weil, imposes itself on the subject and this requires that the subject engage in a process of interpretation and discernment to grasp the meaning of an encounter. Interactions with the world do not bear labels such as “fear” or “peaceful” but require assessment and evaluation. As with James, then, emotions reflect the embodied judgment of the subject’s appraisal of a situation. Emotions, for Weil, are responsive: “It is incorrect to say that we believe that we are in danger because we are afraid,” she writes with an allusion evocative of James. “On the contrary, one is afraid by virtue of the presence of danger; it is the danger that scares us; but danger is something I read.” Footnote 43 For Weil, the world seizes us and forces us to “read” and interpret its meaning. All sensations are bearers of meaning and value. The young lover who receives a note from his beloved swoons not from handling the paper but because of the meaning disclosed from within its fold. There is nothing inherently terrifying about the sound of glass shattering, but a sound that might not raise an eyebrow when one breaks a glass while doing dishes elicits a rather different response when heard in the middle of the night. For Weil, like James, the way we read and interpret the meanings of events is open to refinement and requires discernment. Our responses to the world are not preconditioned but can, with effort, be changed. As we shall consider, one way of effecting such change and refining how one perceives and responds can be achieved through practices of negative effort.

Let me suggest that James makes two contributions to the category of orthopathy, categories needed to fill in the gaps noted in earlier accounts. First, he foregrounds the intimate relationship between bodily perception and the emotions. There is, as Runyon did appreciate, an empirical basis for orthopathy. John Locke, who influenced John Wesley and Runyon, observed that all cognition begins with sensation. In An Essay Concerning Human Understanding he writes, “There appear not to be any ideas in the mind before the senses have conveyed any in.” Footnote 44 This echoes a scholastic axiom found in Thomas Aquinas’s De veritate: Praeterea, nihil in intellectu nisi prius in sensu (Therefore, there is nothing in the intellect that is not first in the senses). Footnote 45 Thanks to James, we can add that there is nothing in the intellect or in the affect that was not first in the senses (nihil est in intellectu vel affectu nisi prius fuerit in sensu). By refusing to reduce affect only to a sense experience, James regards the body and mind as contributing to the emotions. The picture that emerges is one where emotions are not passive but anticipatory. The psychophysical subject does not simply react to the world but, based on prior experiences and future expectations, is oriented by the emotions to future action. A subject’s shifting emotions reflect the embodied subject’s interaction with and interpretation of the world. These encounters are colored by the subject’s prior experiences and serve to shape the agent’s future action. Thus, emotions are not isolable or isolated mental events but embodied judgments of the subject’s perception of the world. They may be more or less accurate, but emotions register a claim about reality and the ways the world impinges upon and affects the subject. They are interpretations that arise from, as Weil noted, “reading” our world.

Second, affections are personal but not private. To avoid subjectivism, orthopathy acknowledges that emotions are psychophysical appraisals 1) of a shared world 2) using socially shared concepts. Emotions of “anger” or “joy” or “sorrow” are not evolutionarily preprogrammed responses, each one being manifested in a uniform manner. With her “theory of constructed emotions,” Barrett argues that socially or culturally mediated conceptual categories make it possible to identify what one is experiencing. Yet concepts of “anger” or “joy” or “sorrow” both identify the emotion and provide the cultural script for how those emotions are expressed. What makes one angry and how one responds “in anger” play out and are intelligible within a cultural-linguistic nexus, Footnote 46 so we learn the word “anger” and the many ways it can be expressed by interacting with and watching others. Interactions with others provides the language and the cultural expectations for how one emotionally responds. We are, in effect, emotionally formed and, at times, even deformed by exemplars. Growth in orthopathy does not require feeling one emotion but, instead, requires developing finesse in discerning how one’s affective response to any stimuli fits and makes sense within one’s cultural context. Over time and with experience, one learns to discern what James called “functional resemblances” that deepen and nuance one’s sense of how emotions can be manifested within a spectrum of responses. Footnote 47 So, although I do not have direct access to your experiences or affective life, I can learn to discern resemblances or analogies with my repertoire of emotion concepts that provide me with at least an inchoate and always culturally conditioned sense for what you might be going through. Footnote 48

The foregoing leads to a definition: Orthopathy reflects the subject’s cognitive appraisal of and embodied response to stimuli using concepts and categories drawn from one’s social context. One is rightly affected when one’s response is intelligible within a shared cultural framework, even if the response leads one to challenge or expand what is typically expected. Orthopathy, in short, is context-dependent and can be assessed only in relation to the shared social world one occupies. This does not mean that being “affected rightly” requires that the same stimulus will elicit an identical response from each member of a given culture. There exists a complex interplay between past experiences, future expectations, and culturally mediated concepts that shape one’s affective response. What makes “right affection” right is how well the subject interprets and evaluates the situation in a coherent manner. Even if we cannot do so in the heat of the moment, we can offer reasons for why we respond as we do. I grow enraged but, upon reflection and with discernment, realize my response is disproportionate to the target of my anger, so I acknowledge that I have misjudged the situation and apologize. At other times, I discern anger to be eminently appropriate to a rift I detect within my community. “Righteous anger” may, in this case, lead me to challenge my inherited cultural script as I denounce injustice and call for the situation’s redress, even if this makes others uncomfortable. But how does one discern whether one’s responses are appropriate? To complement and complete orthopathy, we need an account of orthoaesthesis.

Orthoaesthesis: Negative Effort’s Goal

If the word orthopathy was unfamiliar, orthoaesthesis must strike the ear as a barbarous neologism. Among philosophers and theologians, it has limited currency. As far as I can tell, it was introduced by Edmund Husserl in Ideas II but, apart from a few references to it elsewhere, has not been developed. Footnote 49 Before explaining how I use it, let me locate it in Husserl’s text.

In Ideas II, Husserl examines the way the embodied subject relates to the world. For him, the body acts as “the medium of all perception; it is the organ of perception and is necessarily involved in all perception.” Footnote 50 Under normal, or “orthoaesthetic,” conditions, we are seldom thematically conscious of the body’s role in perception. Unless something obtrudes, the body “disappears” into the background, thereby allowing us to enact our daily tasks. Footnote 51 Within an orthoaesthetic system, one moves seamlessly because of the surrounding harmony. A seasoned chef, for instance, typically thinks little about wielding her knife. In a normal or orthoaesthetic system, her cutting flows naturally and without much focal awareness—until, that is, she burns her hand. The blistered flesh “feels” different, and this in two ways. Swollen and sore, the skin “feels” different from the unburned area. The chef runs another finger over the burn wound, winces, and tries to go back to work. Here, she discovers the second difference in feeling. The wound creates a breach within the system and forces her to renegotiate her practices. She becomes conscious of the body’s role in hitherto unnoticed engagements. Cutting is awkward, slicing labored, and she hopes the blister heals quickly so things return to their orthoaesthetic condition.

That, in broad strokes, is how Husserl understood orthoaesthesis. Orthoaesthesis describes how we perceive, function within, and interact with the world under normal circumstances. Yet it is often the case that we do not recognize our orthoaesthetic states until they are disrupted by some sort of breakdown. An interruption of “normalcy” brings to the fore what had been recessed and ignored. But—here I move in a new direction—what happens when a breakdown of “normalcy” turns out to be salutary? For example, imagine a music student who acquired a bad habit of holding his violin bow in a certain way. To him, it is “normal.” An experienced teacher would see it as an impediment and correct it. At first, the adjustment is awkward and the student resists, but as his playing improves, he embraces the change. What had been a breakdown becomes a breakthrough into an enhanced mode of musicianship. Increased musical range and better tone confirm the benefit. Indeed, he perceives the difference physically and aurally, growing attuned to subtleties in other musical performances that enable him to nuance his own playing. Growth as a musician requires developing orthoaesthesis, a mode of “right perception” that transforms how one listens to music. The violinist does not hear different melodies, but, as he becomes more discerning, he hears them differently, attuned to hitherto missed nuances. He grows orthoaesthetically.

In what follows, I describe orthoaesthesis as the skill and task needed to complement orthopathy. As a skill, it treats right perception as a way of beholding that allows reality to disclose itself on its terms. As a task, right perception demands self-critical discernment of ruptures within a “normal” system. This unfolds in two stages. First, I draw on Simone Weil and Iris Murdoch to establish the foundation of orthoaesthesis. Second, I try to shift orthoaesthesis into a theological key and show how it might contribute to theological method.

Now, neither Murdoch nor Weil ever invoke “orthoaesthesis.” Yet both would concur that cultivating the skill of right perception is a vital task. For Murdoch, “perception itself is a mode of evaluation.” Footnote 52 She accents its moral significance when she claims that “the selfish self-interestedly casual or callous man sees a different world from that which the careful scrupulous benevolent just man sees.” Footnote 53 What causes the difference in vision? It is, Murdoch writes, the self-insistent clamoring of the “fat relentless ego.” Footnote 54 But what we find in Murdoch is not just a theory about perception but techniques to reorient and purify the egocentric gaze. The following passage gives Murdoch’s diagnosis and proposed treatment of egoism’s myopia:

We are not isolated free choosers, monarchs of all we survey, but benighted creatures sunk in a reality whose nature we are constantly and overwhelmingly tempted to deform by fantasy. Our current picture of freedom encourages a dream-like facility; whereas what we require is a renewed sense of the difficulty and complexity of the moral life and the opacity of persons. We need more concepts in terms of which to picture the substance of our being; it is through an enriching and deepening of concepts that moral progress takes place. Simone Weil said that morality was a matter of attention, not of will. We need a new vocabulary of attention.Footnote 55

This passage contains, in nuce, much of what I want to elaborate. I begin by discussing Murdoch’s sense of the obstacles to clear perception. Next, I consider Weil’s contribution to a new “vocabulary of attention” and the way Murdoch adopts and adapts Weil’s ideas. This leads to an analysis of the practices Murdoch enjoins to correct and clarify perception. Her exercises of attention or “negative effort” gradually reorient the egocentric gaze toward a reality outside of the self, a reality that is beheld justly and lovingly. Rather than telling readers what to perceive, Murdoch tutors them in how to perceive. Without growth in this purified mode of perception that Murdoch and Weil know as “attention,” growth in orthopathy is impossible.

Orthoaesthesis: Obstacles and Opportunities

In essays written in 1959, Murdoch identified “social convention and neurosis” as the enemies of the moral life. Footnote 56 Convention submerges agents in a network of rules and expectations. To be good, here, entails “getting along” and demands little introspection or consideration of life’s difficulties. The neurotic, by contrast, stands apart from others. The neurotic is “enclosed in a fantasy” and incapable of recognizing realities beyond the self. Footnote 57 The result, as Margaret Holland writes, is that both “contribute to a failure to perceive the obscure and complex nature of persons.” Footnote 58 In “On ‘God’ and ‘Good,’ ” Murdoch revisits the neurotic and credits Freud for providing a “doctrine of original sin,” albeit one evacuated of supernatural content. Freud, she says, saw the “fallen” agent as “an egocentric system of quasi-mechanical energy, largely determined by its own individual history, whose natural attachments are sexual, ambiguous, and hard for the subject to understand or control. Introspection reveals only the deep tissue of ambivalent motive, and fantasy is a stronger force than reason.” Footnote 59 No Edenic picture here! Beguiled by self-serving fantasy, the ego places itself at the center of reality. The reality of others is a threat, eliciting a hostility manifested in attempts to “derealise the other, devour and absorb him, subject him to the mechanism of our own fantasy.” Footnote 60 Murdoch’s fat ego exercises itself in an anxious and self-assertive libido dominandi.

Yet the fallen subject is not without hope. Murdoch sees the task of moral philosophy as redirecting the ego’s “quasi-mechanical energy” away from the self, a redirection drawn and guided by the purifying pull of another energy. This involves embarking on a spiritual pilgrimage leading “from appearance to reality.” Footnote 61 Fantasy enthralls us with false pictures; it woos with the sirens’ song and lulls one into a state where growth or conversion becomes unthinkable. The purified imagination, by contrast, is liberated from this enchantment. Freed from fantasy, the liberated imagination enables the subject to behold and engage rightly with the world. For Murdoch, the fantasy-free imagination “appears as a restoration of freedom, cognition, the effortful ability to see what lies before one more clearly, more justly, to consider new possibilities, and to respond to good attachments and desires which have been in eclipse.” Footnote 62 Imagination turns toward a reality beyond the self, not to derealize it but to behold it. For Murdoch, this is love: “Love is the perception of individuals. Love is the extremely difficult realisation that something other than oneself is real. Love, and so art and morals, is the discovery of reality.” Footnote 63 Hardly a private emotion, Murdoch’s understanding of love is a radical claim about how we relate to reality.

Egoistic fantasy impedes and blinds the subject’s clear perception. For Murdoch, the “relentless ego” imposes itself on what is other to the self and occludes the subject’s vision. Given its fantasy-fueled libido dominandi, how can one be freed to roam imagination’s expanses and perceive reality with a just and loving gaze? Unlike Baron Munchausen, one cannot save oneself from drowning in fantasy by pulling oneself up by the hair. One must grasp something beyond oneself or, perhaps for the theist, be grasped by something other than the self. Regardless, Murdoch acknowledges that liberation from egoism requires effort and persistence: “It is a task to come to see the world as it is.” Footnote 64 If this is true, orthoaesthesis requires learning to recognize and receive what is other to ourselves. To appreciate this task and how Murdoch suggests achieving it, let us consider the liberating power of the Good before considering Weil’s contribution to Murdoch’s project.

Love, Murdoch claims, “is knowledge of the individual,” Footnote 65 yet she admits that this knowledge is frustrated by the urge to derealize the other. But there are ways to subvert egoism. Evoking Plato’s cave, Murdoch frames human life as a spiritual journey, a redemptive ascent out of egoism’s darkness into a world illuminated by a Good beyond being. Neither an object nor an entity, Murdoch’s understanding of the Good bears a Platonic trace that depicts it as the transcendent “source of light” that enables one to see and evaluate rightly. Footnote 66 Here, her cognitivist slip shows, for “Good” is not a label we simply subjectively affix to objects or actions; as G. E. Moore held, the Good is a real and knowable property. Footnote 67 Good is not denominated by our whim but is, instead, an independent, transcendent, and nonobjectifiable reality by whose light we perceive rightly and know truly. Murdoch believes the solipsistic agent needs to be opened to and reoriented by the Good. Indeed, by its light we discover an idea of perfection that orients and magnetically draws our gaze. By this light, we can behold individual objects’ imperfections and imagine how they could be perfected. The idea of perfection renders every act of evaluation a moral act, for evaluation requires us to judge against a standard. But because we are naturally selfish, seeing what is other to us does not come easily. We must work at seeing clearly. To articulate these practices, Murdoch borrows from Weil the concept of “attention.”

Weil’s definition of attention is found in her “Reflections on the Right Use of School Studies.”Footnote 68 She describes how the mistakes we make in our studies result from egoism. If we rush, if we “seize upon an idea too hastily,” then we close ourselves off from the truth.Footnote 69 Instead of allowing the object to set the method and guide our inquiry, we impose ourselves upon and try to wrest the answer from it. Attention, for Weil, is key because it subdues this egoism. Attention

consists of suspending our thought, leaving it detached, empty, and ready to be penetrated by the object; it means holding in our minds, within reach of this thought, but on a lower level and not in contact with it, the diverse knowledge we have acquired which we are forced to make use of…. Above all[,] our thought should be empty, waiting, not seeking anything, but ready to receive in its naked truth the object that is to penetrate it.Footnote 70

Attention is an active passivity of the self who willingly undergoes a change enacted from outside of the self. Weil embraces paradox, regarding attention as “an effort, the greatest of all efforts perhaps, but it is a negative effort.”Footnote 71 Negative effort requires not an exercise of the will but its opposite: a relaxed openness to reality. For Weil, negative effort should not be enervating but enlivening because it brings us into contact with the real. We learn more, she holds, from twenty minutes of attention than from three hours of struggle. As a training for life, the negative effort exercised through studies prepares us to receive the truth, to welcome God, whenever and however revealed. Pure attention is the substance of prayer and puts us into communion with the world and, for Weil, with God. It assumes a stance of humility and “stands back” in openness to await the other’s self-disclosure. Negative effort quiets the clamoring ego and patiently awaits the advent of the other.

Numerous passages within Weil’s “Forms of the Implicit Love of God” leave little doubt that the French mystic exercised an enormous influence on Murdoch’s thought. I select but one passage to show how Weil’s insight into ego, fantasy, and love presage Murdoch’s work. We live, Weil writes, in a world of

unreality and dreams. To give up our imaginary position as the center, to renounce it, not only intellectually but in the imaginative part of our soul, that means to awaken to what is real and eternal, to see the true light and hear the true silence…. To empty ourselves of false divinity, to deny ourselves, to give up being the center of the world in imagination, to discern that all points in the world are equally centers and that the true center is outside the world, this is to consent to the rule of mechanical necessity in matter and of free choice in the center of each soul. Such consent is love. Footnote 72

Murdoch borrows from Weil’s vocabulary in at least two ways. First, she takes “attention” to express the idea of “a just and loving gaze directed at an individual.” Footnote 73 By no means is attention voyeuristic, for the beholder is also beheld. Attention renders the subject vulnerable to reality and open to transformation. Murdoch calls this transformation wrought through contemplative attention “unselfing.” Footnote 74 Despite the name, it does not mean self-destruction. Rather, it describes an ongoing process of becoming porous to reality. Unselfing, an active and deliberate process, does not require “renouncing the work of our minds on reality altogether.” Footnote 75 If the “fat” ego turns in on the self, unselfing coaxes it open to perceive the world not by the light of fantasy but beneath the light of the Good. Unselfing makes it possible to see justly and lovingly. Attention transforms perception not by homing in on details but by being attuned to the full and irreducible reality of the other. The loving gaze resists efforts to derealize the other; it does not surrender to sentimental romanticism but insists on beholding the other as the other self-manifests. The practice of attention and the active cultivation of a just and loving gaze opens a two-way movement between self and other, allowing the other’s reality to penetrate and transform one’s own reality. To perceive the other rightly, bereft of fantasy’s lenses, may impel one to throw open one’s door in welcome; it may, conversely, embolden one to bar the door to one who threatens to betray love. For if the practiced loving gaze renders one a skilled discerner, it does not enjoin one to become a doormat.

As envisioned by Weil and Murdoch, negative effort involves two movements. Attention arrests the ego’s effort to derealize others and encourages one to become actively passive and receptive to reality. In this pose, the reality of the other may touch one’s very core, but the agent’s actively passive “being open” is simultaneously possible only because the agent is being opened by the Good or God. By this light, the opened subject beholds reality anew and is able “to see, and cherish and respect, what is not” oneself. Footnote 76 Magnetically drawn by the Good, the agent “perceives the real world, a true and just seeing of people and human institutions, which is also a seeing of the invisible through the visible, the real through the apparent, the spiritual beyond the material.” Footnote 77 Now, how Weil and Murdoch interpret this conversion differs. Weil sees “negative effort” as attuning us to creation as a sacrament. The world, for her, is a metaxu, or “between,” where the “essence of created things is to be intermediaries” leading to a transcendent God. Footnote 78 Murdoch, who did not seem to have a belief in a personal God, takes a different approach. For her, the Good functions in a matter akin to Plato’s sun. As she reads Plato, the sun is “separate and perfect, yet also immanent in the world as the life-giving magnetic genesis of all our struggles for truth and virtue.” Footnote 79 Justin Broackes describes Murdoch’s immanent and nonsupernatural Good as “realist and deflationary.” Footnote 80 For Murdoch, Broackes contends, the Good does not hover in a far-off realm, but it is a real property by whose light the moral agent discovers “in lesser goods the shadow of higher degrees of goodness.” Footnote 81 It conveys an idea of perfection, one that gives us a way to distinguish between the “better” and “worse.” Unlike Weil, for whom creation serves as a means to ascend toward the Creator, Murdoch’s Good does not offer a way to an other-worldly vision. It reveals, instead, the world’s texture and allows us to see the world otherwise, as charged or saturated with value. Nevertheless, despite this fundamental disagreement, Weil and Murdoch align in their belief that we can develop right perception. Let us look, then, at examples of how practices of “negative effort” encourage orthoaesthesis.

Contemplated attentively, experiences of beauty can change consciousness. Murdoch provides the following instance:

I am looking outside my window in an anxious and resentful frame of mind, oblivious of my surroundings, brooding perhaps on some damage done to my prestige. Then suddenly I observe a hovering kestrel. In a moment everything is altered. The brooding self with its hurt vanity has disappeared. There is nothing now but kestrel. And when I return to thinking of the other matter it seems less important.Footnote 82

The kestrel interrupts anxious self-preoccupation by shifting her gaze from inner brooding to outward contemplation. Its inbreaking frees the subject from resentment, reinscribes her into the environment, and reintegrates the riven self; it “breaks the spell of this ego-driven oblivion.”Footnote 83 The kestrel’s arrival does not erase the past, but its ingress reorients her vision and makes it possible for her to regard and evaluate her hurts in a new manner. What had moments before constricted and choked her imagination is unclogged; she beholds these events against a new or, at least, a renewed horizon. Despite being a chance encounter and not the result of intentional practice, Murdoch concludes, “this is something which we may also do deliberately: give attention to nature in order to clear our minds of selfish care.”Footnote 84

Murdoch recognizes that affection (anxious brooding) shapes perception (oblivious of surroundings) and its reversal through attention. The kestrel occasions unselfing, a process that does not reduce but renews. It pierces the self-enclosed subject, lifts the veil concealing reality, and enables her to perceive within a broader horizon. Past hurts are recontextualized; their control over her, lessened. The kestrel’s unexpected inbreaking marks a breakthrough into a new mode of openness to what is other. The sudden reorientation of perception is accompanied by a sudden transformation of her affections.

In addition to contemplating physical beauty—natural and artistic—Murdoch envisions other practices of negative effort. Instead of describing the study of Latin or Greek, as Weil did, Murdoch recounts learning Russian. This intellectual practice is no less an occasion for an unselfing, because learning a language requires facing

an authoritative structure which commands my respect. The task is difficult and the goal is distant and perhaps never entirely attainable. My work is a progressive revelation of something which exists independently of me. Attention is rewarded by a knowledge of reality. Love of Russian leads me away from myself towards something alien to me, something which my consciousness cannot take over, swallow up, deny or make unreal. The honesty and humility required of the student—not to pretend to know what one does not know—is the preparation for the honesty and humility of the scholar who does not even feel tempted to suppress the fact which damns his theory.Footnote 85

Attention’s double-movement operates as love’s gaze turns from the self toward a reality it cannot control. The learner must remain open and vulnerable to the language if progress is to be made. For learning demands practice, and though this practice may be perfective, one will never achieve total perfection: the goal of perfection is approached asymptotically. Through study, one grows adept, struggles, and strives, but one’s intellective reach exceeds its grasp. There is, contrary to the ego’s attempt to assert total mastery, always more to know.

Regardless of its object, attention makes communion with reality possible. Unselfing proceeds according to an exitus-reditus pattern. First, one turns away from the self and toward the reality of another (exitus). In this turning, one suppresses egoism by making a concerted effort to see reality on its terms, not the self’s. Then, one returns to the self to discover that one has changed, that one perceives and is now affected by reality differently (reditus). Entering communion with reality, while certainly informative, is also formative. The kestrel, a new language, even my beloved: attention may augment what one knows but, by occasioning growth in love’s gaze, love also transforms how one does so. The student’s humility before reality, inculcated through attention, translates into the expert’s humility whose commitment to the Good empowers her to abandon a pet theory when confronted with contrary evidence. Negative effort capacitates an obediential freedom; growth in “right perception” enables one to discern and pursue the Good more fully. Such discernment leads to the paradoxical realization that authentic freedom derives not from a proliferation of choices but through obedience to the Good.Footnote 86 Maturation in orthoaesthesis engenders an ever-greater fidelity to the real as apperceived according to the light of the Good. This maturation process, moreover, never ends, as the gaze can never exhaust the depths of what is perceived. Whereas a reductive gaze assays to “take the measure” of what is beheld, the orthoaesthetic gaze is drawn into the infinite depths of each being.

“I can only choose within a world I can see[,] in the moral sense of ‘see’ which implies that clear vision is a result of moral imagination and moral effort.”Footnote 87 In Murdoch’s Weil-inspired techniques, we find exercises aimed at clarifying vision. By loosening egoism’s grasp, practices of negative effort transform how we perceive, and are affected by, the real. This process of being liberated from the ego is never completed; it is an ongoing and lifelong task. Bridget Clarke asks whether we can test perception’s veracity. No, not if veracity means claiming dominion over “the Truth.” Yes, if we accept that as individuals and communities we can be “guided by the principle of the Good and the standard of perfection it entails.”Footnote 88 Our pilgrimage from fantasy to reality requires us to undertake a process of ongoing critique. For refining and purifying vision, discernment of social frameworks is no less vital than personal reflection. We grow as perceivers by checking our vision against our frameworks of understanding, by revisiting and rethinking our way of picturing the world, and by being open to modifying those frameworks and pictures. The world, Murdoch writes, is not “given to us ‘on a plate’ ” but as a creative task. Our ongoing task is to learn to see rightly, to see justly, and to see lovingly. The technique for overcoming our egoism is the negative effort of unselfing.Footnote 89

Exercising negative effort is an endless task because cultivating a disciplined moral imagination involves recognizing that there is more than we can ever fully apprehend: there is always too much to take in all at once. The more we refine how we perceive reality, the better able we are to evaluate and respond to it. This leads me to posit the following: Orthoaesthesis, the fruit of negative effort, describes how the attentive beholder stands before reality in a way that is willingly vulnerable to knowing and being affected by what is other to the self. Right perception does not depend on the capacity to see with granular precision but, rather, to take in the whole of what is other on its own terms. The orthoaesthetic subject recognizes that what one perceives is always shaped and colored by one’s affective state, that past experiences and future expectations inform how one comports oneself and interacts with the world in the present. The orthoaesthetic state is not fixed but dynamic and requires critical dialogue with others to verify one’s perceptions, to evaluate one’s responses, and to grow more adept at discerning how better to be affected by and to respond to the world. Guided by the Good or, theologically, by God’s grace, one’s effort to see the individual with a just and loving gaze is rewarded with an ever-deepening knowledge of reality as it is and as it is coming to be. When combined with orthopathy, orthoaesthesis describes a dynamic way of interacting with and responding to one’s world. The two are ineluctably bound such that there can be no orthopathy without orthoaesthesis.

Conclusion

My interest in orthopathy was piqued by Sobrino’s theology, but, as I indicated, his account of the “right way of being affected by Christ” did not provide a satisfactory account of the emotions, nor, despite adducing the role of orthopathy, did the accounts provided by Runyon, Selak, Butner, or Vacek. This underdeveloped aspect of orthopathy led me to attempt to clarify orthopathy’s content, hence my attempt to engage William James’s theory of the emotions to understand better how emotions bear cognitive content. Revisiting James’s theory in the wake of Barret and Ellsworth served to foreground the reciprocal relationship between perception and emotion, aesthesis and pathos. Orthopathy and orthoaesthesis are inseparable yet irreducible: each informs and dynamically forms the other. Finally, by engaging Weil and Murdoch, I tried to provide a foundation for understanding orthoaesthesis as an ongoing task and skill. Practices of “negative effort” are not quick fixes but, rather, progressive and perfective undertakings intended to transform how one beholds the world. I cannot claim that either Weil or Murdoch would be convinced by my account of orthoaesthesis, but I would hope they would approve of my effort to uncover the deep connection between perception and affection.

To be sure, I do not believe practices of orthoaesthesis require an appeal to theology to be complete. Murdoch, an atheist, enjoined her practices by appealing to a version of Plato’s Good, not to God. My argument, rather, is that theologians need an account of orthoaesthesis—and its ineluctable connection to orthopathy—if further work is to be done on how personal or religious experience can be a locus for theological reflection. Theological anthropology cannot talk about the human in the abstract but must account for the fullness of the subject’s embodied existence, an existence that shapes and is shaped by mental and spiritual experience. We cannot treat the emotions as epiphenomenal because they are integrally linked to how one perceives, responds to, and comports oneself within the world. Theological reflection on the relationship between orthoaesthesis and orthopathy will, I believe, enrich the concepts through which theologians experience and understand the world.

“A loving, just gaze cherishes and adds substance,” Murdoch writes, whereas “a contemptuous gaze withers.” Footnote 90 For the Christian beholder whose senses have been touched by charity, the graciously attuned gaze does not impose value on reality but, rather, invites reality to disclose its innermost depths on its terms. The contemplative gaze recognizes the haecceity, or “thisness,” of what is beheld. So, whereas the contemptuous gaze “withers” and diminishes what is other to the self, the orthoaesthetic gaze welcomes the self-manifestation of the other. The orthopathic response, accordingly, strives not to constrain the other but to allow the self to be addressed and called by the other who stands beyond the self. The animating desire of the orthopathic heart seeks not control over but communion with the other in whom, with eyes opened by grace, one detects intimations of the Creative Other.

Paul, in his Letter to the Ephesians, captures the way grace orthoaesthetically attunes recipients to behold creation’s innermost depths. For Paul understands that the Holy Spirit does not assay to turn the graced subject into something new but to renew the subject to behold all things anew. The Spirit, as it were, liberates the agent from the narrow confines of the egoistic self, liberating one to take part in the new creation’s unfolding. Paul describes this maieutic process: “Now to him who by the power at work within us is able to accomplish abundantly far more than all we can ask or imagine” (Eph 3:20, NRSV). This “power at work within us” opens the eyes to see “more and not less.” Johann Baptist Metz describes the “mysticism of open eyes” that makes “all invisible and inconvenient suffering, and—convenient or not—pays attention to it and takes responsibility for it.” Footnote 91 Only when one perceives those who are otherwise invisible, only when one hears the stifled cries of the poor, can one be moved orthopathically to struggle in solidarity as members of Christ’s body. Thus, the mysticism of open eyes finds its complement in the mysticism of the orthopathic heart. The result is a theological way of life, a radical witness that arises, as Jon Sobrino observed, through an encounter with Christ whose grace renews the senses and opens the heart to respond fully to the inbreaking of God’s reign. To be orthopathically affected by Christ, to be of the same mind that was in Christ Jesus (Phil 2:5, NRSV), is to be drawn into a gracious poiēsis that allows one to perceive (aesthesis) and be moved as Christ was moved, to love as Christ loved, to be affected by the cry of the poor as Christ was affected by their cries. The graced orthoaesthetic subject perceives with senses attuned by faith and, through one’s body, mediates to others an encounter with the Christ who, by grace, “lives in me” (Gal 2:20, NRSV).

Love of neighbor, Simone Weil wrote, requires asking, “What are you going through?” Footnote 92 This question captures the essential link between orthopathy and orthoaesthesis. For the loving gaze apprehends the individual, not to derealize or control her, but to bid her welcome. Pose this question to the hungry, the ill, or the imprisoned, and risk discovering, as in Matt 25, that you ask it of the Lord unveiled in the least of our brethren. Practices of negative effort, inspired by Murdoch and Weil, have the potential of awakening what James saw as “a feeling of being in a wider life than that of this world’s selfish little interests; and a conviction, not merely intellectual, but as it were sensible, of the existence of an Ideal Power.” Footnote 93 Theological theory, through practices of negative effort, flowers into a theological way of knowing, a theologically enriched way of life. In an age skeptical of prayer, perhaps we have less need for a “new evangelism” than for renewed practices of negative effort. For it will be through the disciplined practices of negative effort, of allowing what is other to the self to be revealed on the other’s terms, that we may discern in the advent of the other the approach of the Holy One who, to the orthoaesthetically attuned, is no stranger.

References

1 Theologians trail philosophers in addressing this topic, but its literature grows. Classic treatments include Thomas Aquinas on the “passions” in Summa Theologiae 1a, 2ae; Friedrich Schleiermacher, The Christian Faith (ed. Catherine Kelsey and Terrence Tice; Louisville: Westminster John Knox, 2016); Jonathan Edwards, The Religious Affections (ed. John Smith; The Works of Jonathan Edwards 2; New Haven: Yale University Press, 1959); Rudolf Otto, The Idea of the Holy (trans. John Harvey; New York: Oxford University Press, 1958); Edith Stein, On the Problem of Empathy (trans. Waltraut Stein; Washington, DC: ICS Publications, 1989); Martha Nussbaum, Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of Emotions (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2001); Charles Taylor, Sources of the Self (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1989); Peter Goldie, The Emotions: A Philosophical Exploration (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000). More theological engagements are found in Simeon Zahl, “On the Affective Salience of Doctrines,” Modern Theology 31 (2015) 428–44; Ole Riis and Linda Woodhead, A Sociology of Religious Emotion (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010); Gregory S. Clapper, John Wesley on Religious Affections: His Views on Experience and Emotion and Their Role in the Christian Life and Theology (Metuchen, NJ: Scarecrow Press, 1989); Diana Fritz Cates, Aquinas on the Emotions (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 2009); Nicholas Lombardo, The Logic of Desire: Aquinas on Emotion (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 2011).

2 Steven Land, Pentecostal Spirituality: A Passion for the Kingdom (New York: Sheffield Academic, 1994) 43.

3 Runyon’s Catholic counterpart is George P. Schner, “The Appeal to Experience,” TS 53 (1992) 40–59.

4 Theodore Runyon, Exploring the Range of Theology (Eugene, OR: Wipf & Stock, 2012) 142. In a note in The New Creation (Nashville: Abingdon Press, 1998), Runyon recounts coining the term “orthopathy” in 1984 at an Emory University Ministers’ Week in an address titled “Conversion—Yesterday, Today, and Tomorrow,” later published as “A New Look at ‘Experience,’ ” Drew Gateway 51.3 (1987) 44–55.

5 Runyon, Exploring, 141 (italics in original).

6 Ibid., 146–55. Runyon develops them also in The New Creation, 146–67.

7 Runyon, Exploring, 155.

8 Examples of thinkers influenced by Runyon can be found in Hal Knight, “John Wesley and the Emerging Church,” Preacher’s Magazine, Lent/Easter 2010, https://web.archive.org/web/20110131223242/http://www.nph.com/nphweb/html/pmol/use.htm; Noel B. Woodbridge, “Living Theologically—Towards a Theology of Christian Practice in Terms of the Theological Triad of Orthodoxy, Orthopraxy and Orthopathy as Portrayed in Isaiah 6:1–8: A Narrative Approach,” HvTSt 66.2 (2010) 1–6.

9 Jon Sobrino, Christ the Liberator (trans. Paul Burns; New York: Orbis Books, 2001).

10 Ibid., 210.

11 Ibid., 212.

12 Ibid., 210.

13 Ibid., 214.

14 Jon Sobrino, “Orthodoxy When the Christ Is Jesus,” Concilium (2014.2) 92–101, at 98.

15 Annie Selak, “Orthodoxy, Orthopraxis, and Orthopathy: Evaluating the Feminist Kenosis Debate,” Modern Theology 33 (2017) 529–48.

16 Ibid., 530.

17 Ibid., 541.

18 D. Glenn Butner, Jr., “Orthodoxy, Orthopraxis, and Orthopathy: Trajectories for Collaborative Scholarship between Economists and Theologians,” Faith and Economics 67 (2016) 85–104, at 88.

19 Ibid., 88–89.

20 Ibid., 94.

21 Edward Vacek, “Orthodoxy Requires Orthopathy: Emotions in Theology,” Horizons: The Journal of the College Theology Society 40 (2013) 218–41.

22 Ibid., 219.

23 Ibid., 220.

24 Ibid., 221.

25 Ibid., 223.

26 John Kaag addresses the relationship between James’s theory of emotional states and mirror neurons in “Getting Under My Skin: William James on the Emotions, Sociality, and Transcendence,” Zygon: Journal of Religion & Science 44 (2009) 433–50. James’s contribution to the emerging field of neurophenomenology and the attention James continues to receive from neuroscientists is discussed in Eugene Taylor, “William James and the Humanistic Implications of the Neuroscience Revolution: An Outrageous Hypothesis,” Journal of Humanistic Psychology 50 (2010) 410–29. Bernard J. Baars describes how current studies in contemporary neuroscience are returning to traditional insights such as James’s in “How Brain Reveals Mind: Neural Studies Support the Fundamental Role of Conscious Experience,” Journal of Consciousness Studies 10.9-10 (2003) 100–114.

27 William James, “What Is an Emotion?,” Mind 9.34 (April 1884) 188–205, at 189–90 (italics in original).

28 Phoebe Ellsworth, “William James and Emotion: Is a Century of Fame Worth a Century of Misunderstanding?,” Psychological Review 10 (1994) 222–29, at 223 (italics in original). Ellsworth’s interpretation of James has not gone unchallenged. For a critical response, see Rainer Reisenzein, Wulf-Uwe Meyer, and Achim Schützwhol, “James and the Physical Basis of Emotion: A Comment on Ellsworth,” Psychological Review 102 (1995) 757–61.

29 James, “What Is an Emotion?,” 190.

30 Ibid., 194.

31 Ellsworth, “William James and Emotion,” 223.

32 C. S. Lewis, A Grief Observed (New York: Harper One, 1994) 3.

33 W. L. Worcester, “Observations on Some Points in James’s Psychology. II. Emotion,” The Monist 3.2 (1893) 285–98, at 287.

34 William James, “The Physical Basis of Emotion,” Psychology Review 1 (1894) 516–29.

35 Ellsworth, “William James and Emotion,” 224 (italics in original).

36 James, “Physical Basis,” 518 (italics added).

37 Lisa Feldman Barrett, How Emotions Are Made: The Secret Life of the Brain (New York: Houghton Mifflin, 2017) 30 (italics in original).

38 John Dewey, “The Theory of Emotion I: Emotional Attitudes,” Psychological Review 1.6 (1894) 553–69.

39 Barrett, How Emotions Are Made, 161. Barrett offers a critique of neuroscientist Antonio Damasio for hewing too closely to Dewey’s James-Lange theory and failing to realize James’s unique approach. I forgo a discussion of the vast secondary literature because it exceeds the scope of the article. My goal here is to provide an account of the emotions that could be serviceable for an understanding of orthopathy. It is not the only account, and it may not be the best. Given the pioneering work of Lisa Feldman Barrett and her recognition of how James’s theory has often been misrepresented, I opt for giving James a chance to contribute to our understanding of the emotions.

40 James, “What Is an Emotion?,” 191.

41 Barrett, How Emotions Are Made, 141.

42 James, “Physical Basis,” 520.

43 Simone Weil, “Essay on the Notion of Reading” (trans. Chris Fleming), The Journal of Continental Philosophy 1 (2020) 9–15, at 12 (italics added).

44 John Locke, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding (ed. Roger Woolhouse; New York: Penguin Classics, 1998) bk. 2, ch. 1, par. 23.

45 Thomas Aquinas, Questiones Disputatae de Veritate (trans. Robert Mulligan; Chicago: Henry Regnery, 1952) q. 2, art. 3, 19.

46 Lisa Feldman Barrett supports James’s theory in “Emotions Are Real,” Emotion 12 (2012) 413–29.

47 James, “Physical Basis,” 520.

48 On Barrett and Gendron’s “theory of constructed emotion,” see Maria Gendron and Lisa Feldman Barrett, “Emotion Perception as Conceptual Synchrony,” Emotion Review 10 (2018) 101–10.

49 Edmund Husserl, Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Psychology, Second Book (trans. Richard Rojcewicz and André Schuwer; Boston: Kluwer Academic, 1989) 70–80. I develop this in Ryan Duns, Spiritual Exercises for a Secular Age: Desmond’s Quest for God (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 2020).

50 Husserl, Ideas II, 61 (italics in original).

51 Drew Leder, The Absent Body (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990) 26–27.

52 Iris Murdoch, Metaphysics as a Guide to Morals (New York: Penguin Books, 1992) 315.

53 Ibid., 175.

54 Iris Murdoch, Existentialists and Mystics: Writings on Philosophy and Literature (New York: Penguin Books, 1997) 342.

55 Ibid., 293.

56 Murdoch, “The Sublime and the Good” and “The Sublime and the Beautiful Revisited,” in Existentialists, 205–20 and 261–86.

57 Murdoch, Existentialists, 216.

58 Margaret Holland, “Obstacles to Moral Freedom,” in Iris Murdoch, Philosopher (ed. Justin Broackes; New York: Oxford University Press, 2014) 259.

59 Murdoch, Existentialists, 341.

60 Ibid., 417.

61 Murdoch, Metaphysics, 10.

62 Ibid., 321–22.

63 Murdoch, Existentialists, 215.

64 Ibid., 375 (italics in original).

65 Ibid., 321.

66 Ibid., 357.

67 Maria Antonaccio, Picturing the Human: The Moral Thought of Iris Murdoch (New York: Oxford University Press, 2000) 115–23. Murdoch challenges the fact-value distinction in “Vision and Choice in Morality,” in Murdoch, Existentialists, 76–98.

68 Simone Weil, Waiting for God (trans. Emma Crawford; New York: First Perennial Classics, 2001) 57–65.

69 Ibid., 62.

70 Ibid.

71 Ibid., 61.

72 Ibid., 100.

73 Murdoch, Existentialists, 327.

74 The idea of “unselfing” has met criticism, especially due to the way Weil’s “decreation” influences Murdoch. Nora Hamalaien responds to Sabina Lovibond’s concerns in her essay “Reduce Ourselves to Zero? Sabina Lovibond, Iris Murdoch, and Feminism,” Hypatia 30 (Fall) 743–59. Eric Springsted, in Simone Weil for the Twenty-First Century (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 2021) 66–67, develops the connection between apophatic theology and decreation.

75 Maria Antonaccio, A Philosophy to Live By: Engaging Iris Murdoch (New York: Oxford University Press, 2012) 168.

76 Murdoch, Metaphysics, 17.

77 Ibid., 475.

78 Simone Weil, Gravity and Grace (trans. Emma Crawford and Mario van der Ruhr; New York: Routledge, 2002) 145.

79 Murdoch, Metaphysics, 38.

80 Justin Broackes, introduction to Iris Murdoch, Philosopher (ed. Broackes), 59. Murdoch (Metaphysics, 475) writes, “Plato’s view of the good and virtue are not to be understood in any supernatural sense.”

81 Antonaccio, Picturing, 127.

82 Murdoch, Existentialists, 369. This example has theological precedent in Weil, Waiting, 125.

83 Mark Freeman, “Beholding and Being Beheld: Simone Weil, Iris Murdoch, and the Ethics of Attention,” The Humanistic Psychologist 43 (2015) 160–72, at 167.

84 Murdoch, Existentialists, 369.

85 Ibid., 373.

86 Ibid., 331.

87 Ibid., 329.

88 Bridget Clarke, “Iris Murdoch and the Prospects for Critical Moral Realism,” in Iris Murdoch, Philosopher (ed. Broackes), 251.

89 Murdoch, Metaphysics, 215.

90 Murdoch, Metaphysics, 463.

91 Johann Baptist Metz, A Passion for God: The Mystical-Political Dimensions of Christianity (trans. J. Matthew Ashley; New York: Paulist, 1989) 163.

92 Weil, Waiting, 64.

93 William James, The Varieties of Religious Experience: A Study in Human Nature (New York: Barnes & Noble Classics, 2004) 240.

Figure 0

Figure 1.