Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-c47g7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-23T22:17:58.184Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

CORRUPTION IN ADVERSARIAL SYSTEMS: THE CASE OF DEMOCRACY

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  09 May 2019

Daniel M. Weinstock*
Affiliation:
Law, McGill University

Abstract:

In this essay I argue that adversarial institutional systems, such as multi-party democracy, present a distinctive risk of institutional corruption, one that is particularly difficult to counteract. Institutional corruption often results not from individual malfeasance, but from perverse incentives that make it the case that agents within an institutional framework have rival institutional interests that risk pitting individual advantage against the functioning of the institution in question. Sometimes, these perverse incentives are only contingently related to the central animating logic of an institution. In these cases, immunizing institutions from the risk of corruption is not a theoretically difficult exercise. In other cases, institutions generate perverse or rival incentives in virtue of some central feature of the institution’s design, one that is also responsible for some of the institution’s more positive traits. In multi-party democratic systems, partisanship risks giving rise to too close an identification of the partisan’s interest with that of the party, to the detriment of the democratic system as a whole. But partisanship is also necessary to the functioning of such a system. Creating bulwarks that allow the positive aspects of partisanship to manifest themselves, while offsetting the aspects of partisanship through which individual advantage of democratic agents is linked too closely to party success, is a central task for the theory and practice of the institutional design of democracy.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Social Philosophy and Policy Foundation 2019 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

*

I would first like to thank the other contributors to this volume, as well as two anonymous reviewers for Social Philosophy and Policy, for useful comments that improved the essay immeasurably. I would also like to thank David Schmidtz for his patience and forbearance when an episode of ill health threatened its completion.

References

1 Leslie Holmes reports that according to a recent international poll, it has been identified as the world’s number one political problem. Holmes, Leslie, Corruption: A Very Short Introduction (Oxford : Oxford University Press, 2015), i.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

2 The appeal for political theorists to attend to the actual conduct of politics was, of course, central to Jeremy Waldron’s Inaugural Lecture as Chichele Chair at Oxford University. See his “Political Political Theory,” in Political Political Theory (Cambridge, MA : Harvard University Press, 2016).

3 Warren, Mark, “ What Corruption Means in a Democracy,” in American Journal of Political Science 48, no. 2 (2004): 328–43CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Warren, Mark, “The Meaning of Corruption in Democracies,” in Heywood, P. M., ed., Routledge Handbook of Political Corruption (London: Routledge, 2015), 4255.Google Scholar

4 For example, see Warren, op. cit ; Thompson, Dennis F., “Two Concepts of Corruption,” Edmund J. Safra Working Papers, no. 16, 2013CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Ceva, Emanuela and Ferretti, Maria Paola, “Liberal Democratic Institutions and the Damages of Political Corruption,” in The Ethics Forum 9, no. 1 (2014), 126–45.Google Scholar For an attempt to combine individualist and institutional accounts with which my account has some similarities, see Miller, Seumas, “Corruption,” in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, rev. ed., published 2011).Google Scholar

5 According to widely accepted accounts of public service in Guatemala that I received when I taught there in the early 2000s, the risks involved in taking up any position in the public service were such that one could not reasonably expect anyone to do so without additional financial inducement. Moral distinctions were made between “five-percenters,” “ten percenters,” and the like on the basis of lesser or greater bribes insisted upon by different public officials.

6 Néron, Pierre-Yves, “À quoi sert la conception institutionnelle de la corruption?” in The Ethics Forum 9, no. 1 (2014) : 103125.Google Scholar

7 Philp, Mark, “Defining Political Corruption,” in Political Studies XLV (1997): 436–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

8 Pal, Michael and Choudhry, Sujit, “Still Not Equal? Visible Minority Vote Dilution in Canada,” in Canadian Political Science Review 8, no. 1 (2014): 85101.Google Scholar

9 This is not to say that there are not other ways in which it can be criticized because of its marginalization of minority votes.

10 For a general account of the problems inherent in thinking of institutions in terms of incentives, see Grant, Ruth, Strings Attached. Untangling the Ethics of Incentives (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2011).Google Scholar

11 Ryan, James E., “The Perverse Incentives of the No Child Left Behind Act,” in 79 New York University Law Review 932 (2004).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

12 For general concerns about the perverse incentives related to performance indicators, see Propper, Carol and Wilson, Deborah, “The Use and Usefulness of Performance Indicators in the Public Sector,” in Oxford Review of Economic Policy 19, no. 2 (2003): 250–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

13 Miller, op. cit.

14 Aristotle, , The Politics, ed. Reeve, C. D. C. (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing, 2017), bk. V.Google Scholar

15 See, for example, Müller, Jan-Werner, What is Populism? (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2016).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

16 For an early attempt at delineating the ethical challenges associated with adversarial systems, see Applbaum, Arthur, Ethics for Adversaries. The Morality of Roles in Public and Professional Life (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2000).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

17 On the role of the opposition in parliamentary systems, see Waldron, Jeremy, “The Principle of Loyal Opposition,” in Political Political Theory (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2016).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

18 Applbaum, op. cit.

19 For a largely congruent view of the tasks of business ethics, see Heath, Joseph, “An Adversarial Ethic for Business,” in Morality, Competition, and the Firm. The Market Failures Approach to Business Ethics (Oxford : Oxford University Press, 2014).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

20 Cf. Jeremy Waldron, “The Principle of Loyal Opposition.”

21 There has in recent years been an impressive revival of interest in political parties among political theorists. See Rosenblum, Nancy, On the Side of the Angels. An Appreciation of Parties and Partisanship (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2008);Google Scholar Muirhead, Russell, The Promise of Party in a Polarized Age (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2014);CrossRefGoogle Scholar White, Jonathan and Ypi, Lea, The Meaning of Partisanship (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016);CrossRefGoogle Scholar Bonotti, Matteo, Partisanship and Political Liberalism (New York: Oxford University Press, 2017).Google Scholar

22 I have developed the idea of a “platform” as a normative idea in “Integrating Intermediate Goods to Theories of Distributive Justice: The Importance of Platforms,” in Res Publica 21, no. 2 (2015): 171–83.

23 Goodin, Robert, “The Place of Parties,” in Innovating Democracy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

24 On the epistemic function of trials, see Laudan, Larry, Truth, Error, and Criminal Law (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

25 The benefits and disadvantages of partisanship for democratic societies is a central theme of the works by Rosenblum, Muirhead, White and Ypi, and Bonotti.