Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-t5pn6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-19T21:59:04.971Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

“Well-Being, Adaptation and Human Limitations”

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  07 April 2017

Extract

Philosophical accounts of human well-being face a number of significant challenges. In this paper, I shall be primarily concerned with one of these. It relates to the possibility, noted by Martha Nussbaum and Amartya Sen amongst others, that people's desires and attitudes are malleable and can ‘adapt’ in various ways to the straitened circumstances in which they live. If attitudes or desires adapt in this way it can be argued that the relevant desires or attitudes fail to provide a reliable basis for evaluating well-being. This is, what I shall call the ‘adaptation problem’. Nussbaum and Sen have—in different ways used this argument to motivate their versions of the ‘capability approach’. However, questions remain about the implications of adaptation for philosophical accounts of well-being.

Type
Papers
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 2006

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 See, in particular, his Value Judgement: Improving Our Ethical Beliefs (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996).Google Scholar

2 See Griffin, James P., Well-Being: Its Meaning, Measurement and Moral Importance (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), 139.Google Scholar

3 I set aside well-known problems relating to whether the desire account should focus on a person's ‘self-regarding’ desires as well as those that relate to the prospective nature of desires. The problems I discuss arise even if those problems could, somehow, be solved.

4 While weakness of will is very pertinent to human limitations in the context of accounts of well-being, I do not discuss it here since it is already much discussed in the literature. See, for example, my ‘The Concept of Well-Being,’ Economics and Philosophy, 14, No. 1, (04, 1998), 5861.Google Scholar

5 Sidgwick, Henry, The Method of Ethics (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1981), 111112.Google Scholar

6 Brandt, Richard B., Morality, Utilitarianism and Rights (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), 40.Google Scholar

7 A Theory of the Good and the Right, 113.Google Scholar

8 Ibid., 113.

9 Ibid., 116–120 and 122–126.

10 See for example, GriffinJames, P. James, P., Value Judgement: Improving Our Ethical Beliefs (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996), 21Google Scholar and Gibbard, Allan, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990), 18.Google Scholar

11 Well-Being, 14.Google Scholar

12 Ibid., 12–14.

13 Ibid., 13.

14 Ibid., 17.

15 Wayne Sumner also notes the shift in Griffin's thought in Sumner, L.W., ‘Something in Between’, Well-Being and Morality: Essays in Honour of James Griffin Crisp, R. and Hooker, B. (eds.) (Oxford, Clarendon Press, 2000), 24.Google Scholar

16 I am grateful to James Griffin for pointing this out to me.

17 Railton, Peter, ‘Moral Realism’, The Philosophical Review, XCV, No. 2 (04 1986), 173.Google Scholar

18 Ibid., 174.

19 Rosati, Connie, ‘Persons, Perspectives and Full Information Accounts of the Good’, Ethics, 105, No. 2 (01 1995), 310.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

20 Ibid., 315

21 Richard Arneson suggests this response, in Arneson, Richard, ‘Human Flourishing Versus Desire Satisfaction’, Human Flourishing Frankel, E. F., Miller, F. D. Jr, Paul, J. (ed.) (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), 129130.Google Scholar

22 Well-Being, 47.Google Scholar

23 Parfit, Derek, Reasons and Persons (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1984), 493.Google Scholar

24 ‘Human Flourishing Versus Desire Satisfaction’, 133.Google Scholar

25 Ibid., 126.

26 Ibid., 34.

27 Sumner, L.W., Welfare, Happiness and Ethics (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996), 172.Google Scholar

28 Ibid., 145.

29 Ibid., 160.

30 Ibid., 161.

31 Ibid., 162.

32 Sen, Amartya K., On Ethics and Economics (Oxford: Blackwell, 1987), 45–6Google Scholar. For a discussion of Sen's examples see Miriam Teschl and Flavio Comim ‘Adaptive Preferences and Capabilities’, Paper presented at a conference on Capability and Happiness, St. Edmund's College, Cambridge, March 2004.

33 Welfare, Happiness and Ethics, 166Google Scholar

34 Ibid., 170.

35 Indeed, the case of the hardened unemployed may be better understood in terms of ‘social exclusion’ rather than socialization.

36 Ibid., 109.

37 Ibid., 115–7.

38 Ibid., 116.

39 Ibid., 131.

40 Mill, John Stuart, Utilitarianism, On Liberty, Essay on Bentham (ed.) Warnock, M., (Glasgow: William Collins Sons & Co.), 261.Google Scholar

41 Ibid., 113.

42 Ibid., 113.

43 Ibid., 114.

44 Brannmark, Johan, ‘Leading a Life of One's Own: On Weil-Being and Narrative Autonomy,’Google Scholar this volume.

45 ‘Leading a Life of One's Own,’ 77.Google Scholar

46 Ibid., 78.

47 Well-Being, 34.Google Scholar

48 Value Judgement, 23.Google Scholar

49 Harsanyi, John C., ‘Utilities, Preferences and Substantive Goods’, Social Choice and Welfare 14, (1997), 129145Google Scholar. For a comparison of Harsanyi's and Griffin's positions see my, ‘Griffin, Harsanyi and Others at the Fuzzy Borderline Between Economics and Philosophy’, Telos, X, No. 1, (2001), 99119.Google Scholar

50 ‘Utilities, Preferences and Substantive Goods,’ 141.Google Scholar

51 See particularly Griffin, James P., ‘Against the Taste Model’, Interpersonal Comparisons of Well-Being, Elster, J. and Roemer, J. (ed) (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 4569.Google Scholar

52 Value Judgement, 2930.Google Scholar

53 Ibid., 53–4.

54 Ibid., 57–9.

55 Ibid., 58.

56 Ibid., 58.

57 See my ‘The Concept of Well-Being’, 6970.Google Scholar

58 Indeed, if an informed desire account only requires sufficient information to individuate such values (which are seen as the objects of informed desires), it would not ask much of human capacities. Yet, as we have seen, informed desire accounts often go beyond merely listing such values, and involve comparisons between, and information about, various lives a person might lead.

59 ‘Against the Taste Model’, 65.Google Scholar

60 See Rosati, 's ‘Persons, Perspectives and Full Information Accounts of the Good’Google Scholar, and Sobel, David, ‘Full Information Accounts of Weil-Being,’ Ethics 104, (07 1995), 784810.Google Scholar

61 ‘Against the Taste Model’, 66.Google Scholar

62 Griffin's account is nonetheless not best seen as an objective-list theory because he rejects standard versions of the objective/subjective dualism in this context. See Well-Being, 33Google Scholar and Value Judgement, 35–6.Google Scholar

63 I develop a longer list of prudential values—which includes a basic amount of rest and hope or aspiration in my ‘The Concept of Well-Being’, 67.Google Scholar

64 Value Judgement, 30.Google Scholar

65 See Okin, Susan Moller, ‘Poverty, Weil-Being and Gender: Who Counts, Who's Heard?Philosophy and Public Affairs, 31, No. 3, (2003), 3359Google Scholar; Alkire, Sabina, Valuing Freedoms: Amartya Sen's Capability Approach and Poverty Reduction (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000Google Scholar; Clark, David A., Visions of Development (Cheltenham, Edward Elgar, 2002)Google Scholar; and Narayan, Deepa et al. , Voices of the Poor (Washington: World Bank, 2000).Google Scholar

66 See Clark, David's Visions of DevelopmentGoogle Scholar and Okin, Susan Moller's ‘Poverty, Weil-Being and Gender: Who Counts, Who's Heard?’Google Scholar for arguments with this flavour.

67 See Sen, Amartya K., ‘Capability and Well-Being,’ The Quality of Life, Nussbaum, M. and Sen, A. K. (eds.) (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993), 31.Google ScholarPubMed

68 ‘Capability and Well-Being,’ 40–1.Google Scholar

69 See ‘Capability and Well-Being,’ 4649Google Scholar; and Sen, Amartya K., Development as Freedom (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 86Google Scholar. For a discussion of this aspect of Sen, 's work see my ‘Development, Common Foes and Shared Values’, Review of Political Economy, 14, No. 4, 463480.Google Scholar

70 Nussbaum, Martha C., ‘Nature, Function and Capability: Aristotle on Political Distribution’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 6 Supplementary Vol., (1988), 145184.Google Scholar

71 The relevant contributions include Nussbaum, Martha C., ‘Aristotelian Social Democracy’, Liberalism and the Good, Douglass, B., Mara, G. and Richardson, H. (eds.) (London: Routledge, 1990), 203252Google Scholar; and ‘Human Functioning and Social Justice. In Defence of Aristotelian Essentialism’, Political Theory, 20, (1992) 202246.Google Scholar

72 Nussbaum, Martha C., Sex and Social Justice (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999)Google Scholar and Women and Human Development (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000).Google Scholar

73 Women and Human Development, 35.Google Scholar

74 See Sen, Amartya K., Rationality and Freedom (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002).Google Scholar

75 See, in particular, Nussbaum, Martha C., ‘Aristotle on Human Nature and the Foundation of Ethics’, World, Mind and Ethics: Essays on the Ethical Philosophy of Bernard Williams Altham, J. E. J. and Harrison, R. (eds.), (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), 86131.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

76 See Nussbaum, Martha C., The Fragility of Goodness (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986), 373–78.Google Scholar

77 ‘Nature, Function and Capability: Aristotle on Political Distribution,’ 176.Google Scholar

78 Welfare, Happiness and Ethics, 66–7 and 163–4.Google Scholar

79 ‘Capability and Well-Being’, 45–6.Google Scholar

80 ‘Capability and Well-Being’, 31.Google Scholar

81 I develop this argument in my ‘Development, Common Foes and Shared Values’, Review of Political Economy, 14, No. 4, (2002), 468.Google Scholar

82 Sabina Alkire develops such a list influenced by Finnis, John' work in her Valuing Freedoms: Sen's Capability Approach and Poverty Reduction.Google Scholar

83 Women and Human Development, 119148.Google Scholar

84 Ibid., 138.

85 Ibid., 139.

86 Ibid., 116–7.

87 Ibid., 117.

88 Her discussion focusses on Scanlon, Thomas's ‘Value, Desire and the Quality of Life’, The Quality of Life Nussbaum, M.C. and Sen, A.K. (eds.) (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993), 185200.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

89 Ibid., 152.

90 Ibid., 153.

91 Ibid., 157–8.

92 Ibid., 160

93 Ibid., 155–6.

94 Nussbaum, Martha C., ‘On Hearing Women's Voices: A Reply to Susan Okin,’ Philosophy and Public Affairs, 32, No. 2, (2004), 193205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

95 Ibid., 161.

96 Ibid., 165.

97 Nussbaum inevitably discusses ‘consciousness-raising’ in this context, though her discussion is restricted to the experiences of Indian women in self-help groups. See ibid., 161–2.

98 Mill, John Stuart, The Subjection of Women, Okin, S.M. (ed.), (Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett, 1988), 22Google Scholar. On a related issue see my ‘A Weakness of the Capability Approach with Respect to Gender Justice’, Journal of International Development, 9 (0904 1997) 251263.Google Scholar