Hostname: page-component-7c8c6479df-nwzlb Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-03-19T04:43:45.269Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

PEIRCE’S CALCULI FOR CLASSICAL PROPOSITIONAL LOGIC

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 October 2018

MINGHUI MA*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Sun Yat-Sen University
AHTI-VEIKKO PIETARINEN*
Affiliation:
Tallinn University of Technology; Nazarbayev University; and Higher School of Economics, National Research University
*
*DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY INSTITUTE FOR LOGIC AND COGNITION SUN YAT-SEN UNIVERSITY, GUANGZHOU XINGANG XI ROAD 135, HAIZHU DISTRICT GUANGZHOU 510275, CHINA E-mail: mamh6@mail.sysu.edu.cn
TALLINN UNIVERSITY OF TECHNOLOGY, TALLINN NAZARBAYEV UNIVERSITY, ASTANA NATIONAL RESEARCH UNIVERSITY HIGHER SCHOOL OF ECONOMICS MOSCOW, RUSSIA E-mail: ahti-veikko.pietarinen@ttu.ee

Abstract

This article investigates Charles Peirce’s development of logical calculi for classical propositional logic in 1880–1896. Peirce’s 1880 work on the algebra of logic resulted in a successful calculus for Boolean algebra. This calculus, denoted by PC, is here presented as a sequent calculus and not as a natural deduction system. It is shown that Peirce’s aim was to present PC as a sequent calculus. The law of distributivity, which Peirce states in 1880, is proved using Peirce’s Rule, which is a residuation, in PC. The transitional systems of the algebra of the copula that Peirce develops since 1880 paved the way to the 1896 graphical system of the alpha graphs. It is shown how the rules of the alpha system reinterpret Boolean algebras, answering Peirce’s statement that logical graphs supply a new system of fundamental assumptions to logical algebra. A proof-theoretic analysis is given for the connection between PC and the alpha system.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Association for Symbolic Logic 2018 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Anellis, I. (2012). Peirce’s truth-functional analysis and the origin of the truth table. History and Philosophy of Logic, 33, 3741.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Badesa, C. (2004). The Birth of Model Theory: Löwenheim’s Theorem in the Frame of the Theory of Relatives. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Bellucci, F. & Pietarinen, A.-V. (2016). Existential graphs as an instrument for logical analysis. Part 1: Alpha. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 9 (2), 209237. DOI 10.1017/S1755020315000362.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bellucci, F. & Pietarinen, A.-V. (2017). From mitchell to carus: 14 years of logical graphs in the making. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, 52(4), 539575. DOI: 10.2979/trancharpeirsoc.52.4.02.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boole, G. (1847). The Mathematical Analysis of Logic. Cambridge: Macmillan, Barclay & Macmillan.Google Scholar
Boole, G. (1854). An Investigation of the Laws of Thought. Cambridge: Walton & Maberly.Google Scholar
Brady, G. (2000). From Peirce to Skolem: A Neglected Chapter in the History of Logic. Amsterdam: Elsevier.Google Scholar
Brünnler, K. (2003). Deep Inference and Symmetry in Classical Proof. Ph.D. Thesis, Technische Universität Dresden.Google Scholar
Dipert, R. (2004). Peirce’s deductive logic: Its development, influence, and philosophical significance. In Misak, C., editor. The Cambridge Companion to Peirce. Cambridge, Mass: Cambridge University Press, pp. 257286.Google Scholar
Houser, N. (1985). Peirce’s Algebra of Logic and the Law of Distribution, Dissertation. University of Waterloo, Ontario.Google Scholar
Houser, N. (1991). Peirce and the law of distribution. In Drucker, T., editor. Perspectives on the History of Mathematical Logic. Boston: Birkhäuser, pp. 1032.Google Scholar
Houser, N., Roberts, D., & Van Evra, J. (editors) (1997). Studies in the Logic of Charles S. Peirce. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Huntington, E. V. (1904). Sets of independent postulates for the algebra of logic. Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, 5, 288309.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keynes, J. N. (1887). Studies and Exercises in Formal Logic. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Ma, M. & Pietarinen, A.-V. (2017a). Graphical sequent calculi for modal logics. Electronic Proceedings in Theoretical Computer Science, 243, 91103. 10.4204/EPTCS.243.7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ma, M. & Pietarinen, A.-V. (2017b). Gamma graph calculi for modal logics. Synthese, 195, 3621. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1390-3.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ma, M. & Pietarinen, A.-V. (2017c). Peirce’s sequent proofs of distributivity. In Ghosh, S., and Prasad, S., editors. Logic and Its Applications: 7th Indian Conference. Lecture Notes in Computer Science, Vol. 10119. Springer, pp. 168182.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, R. M. (1980). Peirce’s Logic of Relations and Other Studies. Dordrecht: Foris.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mitchell, O. H. (1883). On a new algebra of logic. In Peirce, C. S., editor. Studies in Logic, by Members of Johns Hopkins University, Boston: Little, Brown & Company, pp. 72106.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
De Morgan, A. (1847). Formal Logic. London: Taylor and Walton.Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1867). On an improvement in Boole’s calculus of logic. Proceedings of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences 7, 250261.Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1880). On the algebra of logic. American Journal of Mathematics, 3(1), 1557. (Reprinted in Kloesel, C. J. W., editor. Writings of C. S. Peirce: A Chronological Edition, Vol. 4. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, pp. 163–209.)Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (editor) (1883). Studies in Logic by Members of the Johns Hopkins University. Boston: Little, Brown, and Co.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1885). On the algebra of logic: A contribution to the philosophy of notation. American Journal of Mathematics, 7(2), pp. 180196.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1891a). Algebra of the Copula [Version 1]. In Houser, N., and De Tienne, A., editors. Writings of Charles S. Peirce, Vol. 8 (1890–1892). Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, pp. 210211.Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1891b). Algebra of the Copula [Version 2]. In Houser, N., and De Tienne, A., editors. Writings of Charles S. Peirce, Vol. 8 (1890–1892). Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, pp. 212216.Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1893a). Grand Logic. Division I. Stecheology. Part I. Non Relative. Chapter VIII. The Algebra of the Copula. (R 411)Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1893b). Grand Logic. Chapter XI. The Boolian Calculus. (R 417)Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1893c). Grand Logic. Book II. Division I. Part 2. Logic of Relatives. Chapter XII. The Algebra of Relatives. (R 418)Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1894). Letter to F. Russell. (R L 387)Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1896–1897). On Logical Graphs. (R 482)Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1897). Memoir #1 Algebra of Copula. (R 737)Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1897–1898). On Existential Graphs (EG). (R 485)Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1900). Letter to Christine Ladd-Franklin, November 9, 1900. (R L 237)Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1902). Minute Logic. Chapter III. The Simplest Mathematics (Logic III). (R 430)Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (c.1902). On the Basic Rules of Logical Transformation (R 516)Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1903a). Logical Tracts. No. 1. On Existential Graphs. (R 491)Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1903b). Logical Tracts. No. 2. On Existential Graphs, Euler’s Diagrams, and Logical Algebra. (R 491)Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1903c). Logical Tracts. No. 2. The Rules of Existential Graphs. (R 1589)Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1903d). Lowell Lectures. Lecture I. (R 450, S-27)Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1903e). Lowell Lectures. Lecture I. Graphs: A Little Account. (S-27)Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1903f). Lowell Lectures. Lecture I. The Conventions. (S-28)Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1903g). Lowell Lectures. Lecture IV. (R 467)Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1904a). A Proposed Logical Notation (Notation). (R 530)Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1904b). Letter to E. V. Huntington, February 14, 1904. (R L 210)Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1905). A Logical Analysis of Some Demonstrations in High Arithmetic (D). (R 253)Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1908). One, Two, Three. (R 905)Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1910). Diversions of Definitions, July 20–23, 1910. (R 650)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1931–1966). The Collected Papers of Charles S. Peirce, Vol. 8. Hartshorne, C., Weiss, P., and Burk, A. W., editors. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Cited as CP followed by volume and paragraph number.Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1967). Manuscripts in the Houghton Library of Harvard University, as identified by Richard Robin, Annotated Catalogue of the Papers of Charles S. Peirce, Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1967, and in The Peirce Papers: A supplementary catalogue, Transactions of the C. S. Peirce Society, 7, 3757. Cited as R followed by manuscript number and, when available, page number.Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1976). The New Elements of Mathematics by Charles S. Peirce, Vol. 4. Eisele, C., editor. The Hague: Mouton. Cited as NEM followed by volume and page number.Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1982). Writings of Charles S. Peirce: A Chronological Edition, Vols. 1-8. Kloesel, C. W., editor. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Cited as W followed by volume number and, when available, page number.Google Scholar
Pietarinen, A.-V. (2006). Signs of Logic: Peircean Themes on the Philosophy of Language, Games, and Communication (Synthese Library 329). Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Pietarinen, A.-V. (2015). Exploring the beta quadrant. Synthese, 192, 941970. 10.1007/s11229-015-0677-5.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pietarinen, A.-V. & Bellucci, F. (2014). New light on Peirce’s conceptions of retroduction, deduction and scientific reasoning. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 28(4), 353373. 10.1080/02698595.2014.979667.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Prior, A. N. (1958). Peirce’s axioms for propositional calculus. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 23, 135136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Prior, A. N. (1964). The algebra of the copula. In Moore, E. and Robin, R., editors. Studies in the Philosophy of Charles Sanders Peirce. Amherst: The University of Massachusetts Press, pp. 7994.Google Scholar
Roberts, D. D. (1964). The existential graphs and natural deduction. In Moore, E. and Robin, R., editors. Studies in the Philosophy of Charles Sanders Peirce. Amherst: The University of Massachusetts Press, pp. 109121.Google Scholar
Roberts, D. D. (1973). The Existential Graphs of Charles S. Peirce. The Hague: Mouton.Google Scholar
Russell, B. (1901). Sur la logique des relations avec des applications á la théorie des séries. Revue de mathématiques/Rivista di Matematiche, 7, 115148.Google Scholar
Schröder, E. (1890). Vorlesungen über die Algebra der Logik, Vol. 1. Leipzig: Teubner.Google Scholar
Sowa, J. (2006). Peirce’s contributions to the 21st century. In Schärfe, H., Hitzler, P., and Ohrstrom, P., editors. Proceedings of the 14th International Conference on Conceptual Structures. Lecture Notes in Computer Science, Vol. 4068. Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer-Verlag, pp. 5469.Google Scholar
Turquette, A. (1964). Peirce’s icons for deductive logic. In Moore, E. and Robin, R., editors. Studies in the Philosophy of Charles Sanders Peirce. Amherst: The University of Massachusetts Press, pp. 95108.Google Scholar
Valencia, V. S. (1989). Peirce’s Propositional Logic: From Algebra to Graphs. ILLI prepublication series for logic, semantics and philosophy of language LP-89-08. Amsterdam: University of Amsterdam.Google Scholar
Zeman, J. (1964). The Graphical Logic of Charles S. Peirce. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Chicago.Google Scholar