Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-tj2md Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-20T04:15:52.795Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Easily, At a Glance: Aristotle's Political Optics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  10 September 2010

Abstract

In book VII of the Politics, Aristotle requires that the best regime be eusunoptos, “easily taken in at a glance.” Throughout the history of political thought, the attendant ideal of the polis as a compact and surveyable society was particularly influential. However, closer scrutiny of the way in which Aristotle uses eusunoptos suggests that it designates a problem rather than a solution, to wit, the problems of defining political unity and of attuning the individual and the common good. Exploring the different contexts in which eusunoptos occurs in Aristotle's works, this paper argues that it has political, rhetorical, and poetical meanings that cannot be entirely distinguished from each other. As such, the notion is shown to be germane to the general design of book VII, which constructs the best regime in order to bring to light the limits of politics.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © University of Notre Dame 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 See Harris Rackham's translation in the Loeb Classical Library edition (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2005), and Richard Kraut's translation in the Clarendon Aristotle Series (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1997).

2 Cf. Thucydides The Peloponnesian War 8.66.3.

3 “Synoptic” is used throughout in the primary meaning given by Webster's Collegiate Dictionary: “affording a general view of a whole.” See Laslett, Peter, “The Face to Face Society,” in Philosophy, Politics and Society, ed. Laslett, Peter (Oxford: Blackwell, 1956), 157–48Google Scholar; Finley, Moses I., Politics in the Ancient World (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983), 2829CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Finley, Moses I., Democracy Ancient and Modern (New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press, 1973), 3031Google Scholar.

4 MacIntyre, Alasdair, After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory (London: Duckworth, 1981)Google Scholar; Sandel, Michael, Liberalism and the Limits of Justice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998)CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Cf. Manent, Pierre, Cours familier de philosophie politique (Paris: Fayard, 2001), 7677Google Scholar; Manent, Pierre, “What Is a Nation?The Intercollegiate Review (Fall 2007), 25Google Scholar.

5 Guttmann, Amy, “Communitarian Critics of Liberalism,” in Debates in Contemporary Political Philosophy: An Anthology, ed. Matravers, Derek and Pike, Jonathan E. (London: Routledge, 2003), 182–94Google Scholar.

6 Pitkin, Hanna, The Concept of Representation (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1967)Google Scholar; Barber, Benjamin, Strong Democracy: Participatory Politics for a New Age (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984)Google Scholar.

7 Isocrates Antidosis 15.172. Cf. Ober, Josiah, The Athenian Revolution: Essays on Ancient Greek Democracy and Political Theory (Princeton: Ptrinceton University Press, 1998), 24, 31, 117Google Scholar.

8 Myers, John L., “The Ancient Shape of Attica,” Greece & Rome 12, no. 35/36 (June 1943): 33CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Cf. Nagle, D. Brendan, The Household as the Foundation of Aristotle's Polis (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), 48Google Scholar.

9 Holmes, Stephen T., “Aristippus In and Out of Athens,” in Aristotle's “Politics”: Critical Essays, ed. Kraut, Richard and Skultety, Steven (Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield, 2005), 12Google Scholar. Nevertheless, and somewhat puzzlingly, Holmes subsequently concurs with Finley's assertion that Athens was “a small, homogeneous, relatively closed face-to-face society” (ibid.).

10 Yack, Bernard, The Problems of a Political Animal: Community, Justice, and Conflict in Aristotelian Political Thought (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1993), 73Google Scholar. See also Yack, Bernard, “The Problem of Community,” in Aristotle on Modern Politics: The Persistence of Political Philosophy, ed. Tessitore, Aristide (Notre Dame, IN: Notre Dame University Press, 2002), 33Google Scholar.

11 Osiander, Andreas, Before the State: Systemic Political Change in the West from the Greeks to the French Revolution (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008), 50Google Scholar.

12 Two other occurrences are in disputed works: On Sensation 441a10; On Marvelous Things Heard 838b10.

13 On the connection between limits, order, and beauty, see Aristotle Metaphysics 1078a31–b2; Nicomachean Ethics 1123b6–8.

14 Interestingly enough, the only occurrence of eusunoptos in the Politics before book VII is in a context associated with poetic plot. Referring to the location of the tombs of Philolaus, lawgiver of Thebes, and his lover Diocles, Aristotle tells us: “even now they show their tombs, in full view of each other (allēlois eusunoptous); but one is visible from Corinthian territory, the other not. For they tell the story (muthos) that they planned the sites of the tombs themselves, Diocles so that the land of Corinth with its bitter memories of his suffering should be invisible from his grave, Philolaus that it might be visible from his” (Politics 1274a36–41).

15 Cf. Apollonius Dyscolus On Syntax 2.2.391, 142.

16 Davis, Michael, The Poetry of Philosophy: Aristotle's “Poetics” (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1992), 55Google Scholar.

17 The connection is made by Seth Benardete and Michael Davis in their edition of Aristotle, On Poetics (South Bend, IN: St. Augustine's Press, 2002), 34 n. 85. The only other mention of “prayer” in the Poetics is in 1456b10, where, interestingly enough, it is juxtaposed with “command,” a very political noun indeed.

18 Davis, Michael, The Politics of Philosophy: A Commentary on Aristotle's “Politics” (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1996), 127Google Scholar; Long, Roderick T., “Aristotle's Imaginary Utopia: The Polis Kat' Euchen,” in The Imaginary Polis: Acts of the Copenhagen Polis Center, ed. Hansen, Mogens Herman (Copenhagen: Kgl. Danske Videnskabernes Selskab, 2005), 164–96Google Scholar; Frank, Jill, A Democracy of Distinction: Aristotle and the Work of Politics (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2005), 138–42Google Scholar; Salkever, Stephen, “Whose Prayer? The Best Regime of Book 7 and the Lessons of Aristotle's Politics,” Political Theory 35, no. 1 (2007): 2946CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Mayhew, Robert, “Aristotle on Prayer,” Rhizai. A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science 2 (2007): 295309Google Scholar; Bates, Clifford A., Aristotle's “Best Regime”: Kingship, Democracy and the Rule of Law (Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University Press, 2003)Google Scholar.

19 It may give pause that Aristotle should resort to prayer so emphatically just after he has presented the philosophic life as a model of the happy life.

20 Cf. Burger, Ronna, Aristotle's Dialogue with Socrates: On the “Nicomachean Ethics” (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2008), 285–86 n. 45CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Aristide Tessitore, “MacIntyre and Aristotle on the Foundation of Virtue,” in Aristotle on Modern Politics, 142, 146.

21 See Appian The Foreign Wars XVIII.118; Polybius Histories V.24.6 and VI.49.9; Josephus The Jewish Wars I.57, III.146, 242 and 447.

22 See Aeschines Against Ctesiphon 3.118.

23 Kraut, Richard, Commentary on Aristotle, “Politics” VII and VIII (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1997), 84Google Scholar.

24 P. Manent, Cours familier de philosophie politique, 77. See Janssens, David, “Habeas Corpus? Pierre Manent and the Politics of Europe,” The European Journal of Political Theory 5, no. 2 (2006): 171–90CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

25 According to D. Brendan Nagle, “normal” poleis like Aphytis or Asea, with a citizen body between 230 and 910 citizens representing 200–1000 households, “would have been eusunoptos both in terms of their territory and their population” (The Household as the Foundation of Aristotle's Polis, 56, 74). The lowest number, it is true, would seem to approximate a face-to-face society. However, even for one of 230 citizens to see the others as a surveyable whole would not be easy.

26 For a vivid evocation of this problem, see Keillor's, Garrison hilarious story of Flag Day in Lake Wobegon Days (New York: Viking, 1986), 123–24Google Scholar.

27 Dougherty, James P., “Baroque and Picturesque Motifs in L'Enfant's Design for the Federal Capital,” American Quarterly 26, no. 1 (1974): 23CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

28 Manley, Lawrence, Literature and Culture in Early Modern London (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), 54Google Scholar.

29 See Fredal, James, “Seeing Ancient Rhetoric, Easily at a Glance,” Rhetoric Society Quarterly 36, no. 2 (2006): 181–89CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

30 Cf. Politics 1265a18–19, where Aristotle anticipates the discussion of the best regime and criticizes “the Socratic speeches” for speculating too wildly: “It is proper to set conditions according to prayer (kat' euchēn), but not the impossible.” Ironically enough, “the Socratic speeches” refers to Plato's Laws, from which Socrates is absent.

31 The unusual pleonastic “presupposed in advance” reflects the original Greek (prohupotetheisthai kathaper euchomenous). The verb prohupotithēmi is quite rare in ancient Greek. In fact, its exact meaning—“hypothesized beforehand”—is pleonastic, indeed, just like “pre-supposition” in English.

32 Kraut, Commentary on “Politics,” 77.

33 Cf. Frank, A Democracy of Distinction, 59–61. As Frank explains, the work of the chorēgos chiefly consists in making itself invisible behind the opsis of the spectacle.

34 Kraut, Commentary on “Politics,” 77. Cf. Yack, The Problems of a Political Animal, 242–43.

35 Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, The Social Contract and Other Later Political Writings, ed. and trans. Gourevitch, Victor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), 71Google Scholar.

36 Cf. Frank, A Democracy of Distinction, 12.

37 van Roermund, Bert, Law, Narrative and Reality: An Essay in Intercepting Politics (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic, 1997)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Honig, Bonnie, “Between Decision and Deliberation: Political Paradox in Democratic Theory,” American Political Science Review 101, no. 1 (2007): 117CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Gildin, Hilail, Rousseau's Social Contract: The Design of the Argument (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983), 7071Google Scholar.

38 It is interesting to note that the only two examples of crafts Aristotle supplies in this context are those that Plato coined as metaphors for politics: weaving and seafaring. See Plato Statesman 305e–311c; Republic 488a–489c.

39 See Yack, The Problems of a Political Animal, 263.

40 See Tessitore, “MacIntyre and Aristotle on the Foundation of Virtue,” in Aristotle and Modern Politics, 146.

41 Politics 1255a1–b16. Cf. Politics 1281b24–34; Nicomachean Ethics 1134a.

42 Yack, The Problems of a Political Animal, 76–77; see also 168–69.

43 Cf. Burger, Aristotle's Dialogue with Socrates, 211. Cf. Politics 1334a11–12.

44 Cf. Salkever, “Whose Prayer?” 38–39.

45 Davis, The Politics of Philosophy, 130–31.

46 Cf. Plato Republic 620d.

47 Yack, The Problems of a Political Animal, 170.

48 Davis, The Poetry of Philosophy, xviii. See also his remark that “all action is always already an imitation of action” (ibid.). In this respect, political participants do not differ from spectators of a drama: “drama requires that spectators be induced to attempt to complete the whole before it is complete” (56).

49 See Nichols, Mary P., Citizens and Statesmen: A Study of Aristotle's “Politics” (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1992), 164–65Google Scholar.

50 Cf. Poetics 1447a13–16.

51 In this respect, the construction of the best regime in book VII is comparable to the noble lie that Socrates introduces in Plato's Republic, the Phoenician myth of autochthony designed to constitute political community (Republic 414c–415c).

52 Frank, A Democracy of Distinction, 11.

53 See Yack, The Problems of a Political Animal, 6–7, 16–17, 62–71; Frank, A Democracy of Distinction, 48–49, 64. David Keyt even argues that Aristotle's claim is fundamentally untenable and should be abandoned in favor of the Hobbesian view (Keyt, David, “Three Basic Theorems in Aristotle's Politics,” Phronesis 32, no. 1 [1987]: 5479CrossRefGoogle Scholar).

54 Lefort, Claude, Essais sur le politique: XIXe–XXe siècles (Paris: Éditions du Seuil, 1986), 20Google Scholar; see also 9–10.

55 Ibid., 20, 124, 282.

56 Ibid., 124.

57 Ibid., 14.

58 Frank, A Democracy of Distinction, 12.

59 Historia Animalium 491b9–11. I am indebted to the following people for valuable feedback in writing and revising the present paper: Hans Lindahl, Bert van Roermund, the members of the research group on philosophy of law at the Department of Philosophy of Tilburg University, Clifford Bates, and five anonymous referees.