Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-42gr6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-25T01:16:04.976Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Unified Theories and Unified Science

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

Robert L. Causey*
Affiliation:
The University of Texas at Austin

Extract

Discussions of unified science frequently suppose that the various scientific theories should be combined into one unified theory, and it is usually supposed that this should be done by successive reductions of the various theories to some fundamental theory. Yet, there has been little systematic study of the characteristics of unified theories, and little foundational support for the use of reductions as a unifying procedure.

In this paper I: (a) briefly review some of my previous work on microreductions, (b) state some conditions which are necessary in order for a theory to be unified, (c) argue that when certain identities exist between the elements in the domains of two theories, then the only satisfactory way to combine these two theories into one unified theory is by a microreduction, and (d) indicate briefly some further applications and consequences of this work.

Type
Symposium: The Unity of Science
Copyright
Copyright © 1976 by D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht-Holland

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

*

An earlier version of this paper was presented at the symposium on the Unity of Science at the Fourth Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association at Notre Dame University, November 1-3, 1974. This is a revised draft prepared for publication in this volume.

References

Block, N. J. and Fodor, J. A.: 1972, ‘What Psychological States Are Not’, The Philosophical Review 81, 159181.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bunge, M.: 1967, Scientific Research, Vol. I, Springer-Verlag, New York.Google Scholar
Causey, R. L.: 1969 ‘Polanyi on Structure and Reduction’, Synthese 20, 230237.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Causey, R. L.: 1972a, ‘Attribute-Identities in Microreductions’, The Journal of Philosophy 69, 407-422.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Causey, R. L.: 1972b, ‘Uniform Microreductions’, Synthese 25, 176218.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Causey, R. L.: 1974, ‘Laws, Identities, and Reduction’, forthcoming in the Proceedings of the Conference for Formal Methods in the Methodology of Empirical Sciences, Warsaw, Poland.Google Scholar
Gendron, B.: 1971, ‘On the Relation of Neurological and Psychological Theories: A Critique of the Hardware Thesis’, in Buck, R. C. and Cohen, R. S. (eds.), PSA 1970, D. Reidel Publishing Co., Dordrecht, pp. 483495.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hull, D.: 1974, Philosophy of Biological Science, Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, pp. 139141.Google Scholar
Kalke, W.: 1969, ‘What is Wrong With Fodor and Putnam's Functionalism’, Nous 3, 8393.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oppenheim, P., and Putnam, H.: 1958, ‘Unity of Science as a Working Hypothesis’, in Feigl, H., Scriven, M., and Maxwell, G. (eds.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. II, University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, pp. 336.Google Scholar
Schlesinger, G.: 1963, Method in the Physical Sciences, Humanities Press, New York.Google Scholar