Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-8bhkd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-17T16:18:40.309Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Where Have All the Theories Gone?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

Although the recent emphasis on models in philosophy of science has been an important development, the consequence has been a shift away from more traditional notions of theory. Because the semantic view defines theories as families of models and because much of the literature on “scientific” modeling has emphasized various degrees of independence from theory, little attention has been paid to the role that theory has in articulating scientific knowledge. This paper is the beginning of what I hope will be a redress of the imbalance. I begin with a discussion of some of the difficulties faced by various formulations of the semantic view not only with respect to their account of models but also with their definition of a theory. From there I go on to articulate reasons why a notion of theory is necessary for capturing the structure of scientific knowledge and how one might go about formulating such a notion in terms of different levels of representation and explanation. The context for my discussion is the BCS account of superconductivity, a ‘theory’ that was, and still is, sometimes referred to as a `model'. BCS provides a nice focus for the discussion because it illuminates various features of the theory/model relationship that seem to require a robust notion of theory that is not easily captured by the semantic account.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I would like to thank Michael Dickson for his generous support and comments and two anonymous referees for many helpful suggestions. Support of research by the Social Science and Humanities Research Council of Canada is gratefully acknowledged.

References

Addison, J. W. (1965), “Some Notes on the Theory of Models”, in Addison, J. W., Henkin, L., and Tarski, A. (eds.), The Theory of Models. Amsterdam: North-Holland, 438441.Google Scholar
Bardeen, J. (1951a), “Electron-Vibration Interactions and Superconductivity”, Electron-Vibration Interactions and Superconductivity 23:261270.Google Scholar
Bardeen, J. (1951b), “Relation between Lattice Vibration and London Theories of Superconductivity”, Relation between Lattice Vibration and London Theories of Superconductivity 81:829834.Google Scholar
Bardeen, J. (1973), “History of Superconductivity”, in Kursunoglu, B. and Perlmutter, A. (eds.), Impact of Basic Research on Technology. New York: Plenum.Google Scholar
Bardeen, J., Cooper, L., and Schrieffer, J. R. (1957), “Theory of Superconductivity”, Theory of Superconductivity 108:11751204.Google Scholar
Beth, E. (1949), “Towards an Up-to-Date Philosophy of the Natural Sciences”, Towards an Up-to-Date Philosophy of the Natural Sciences 1:178185.Google Scholar
Braithwaite, R. (1953), Scientific Explanation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Braithwaite, R. (1962), “Models in the Empirical Science”, in Nagle, E., Suppes, P., and Tarski, A. (eds.), Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 224231.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. (1939), Foundations of Logic and Mathematics: International Encyclopedia of Unified Science. Vol. 1, No. 3. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Cartwright, N. (1989), Nature’s Capacities and Their Measurement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cartwright, N. (1999), “Models and the Limits of Theory: Quantum Hamiltonians and the BCS Models of Superconductivity”, in Morgan, M. and Morrison, M. (eds.), Models as Mediators: Perspectives on Natural and Social Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 241281.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cartwright, N., Suarez, M., and Shomar, T. (1995), “The Tool Box of Science”, in Herfel, W. E. et al. (eds.), Theories and Models in Scientific Processes. Amsterdam: Rodopi, 137149.Google Scholar
Cooper, L. (1956), “Bound Electron Pairs in a Degenerate Fermi Gas”, Bound Electron Pairs in a Degenerate Fermi Gas 104:11891190.Google Scholar
da Costa, N. C. A., and French, S. (2003), Science and Partial Truth: A Unitary Approach to Models and Scientific Reasoning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friedman, M. (1982), “Review of van Fraassen The Scientific Image”, Review of van Fraassen The Scientific Image 79:274283.Google Scholar
Frigg, R. (2002), “Models and Representation: Why Structures Are Not Enough.” CPNSS Discussion Paper Series, DP MEAS 25/02.Google Scholar
Frohlich, H. (1950), “Theory of Superconducting State 1: The Ground State at the Absolute Zero of Temperature”, Theory of Superconducting State 1: The Ground State at the Absolute Zero of Temperature 79:845856.Google Scholar
Giere, R. (1988), Explaining Science: A Cognitive Approach. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hesse, M. (1953–54), “Models in Physics”, Models in Physics 4:198214.Google Scholar
Hesse, M. (1970), Models and Analogies in Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, T. (1972), The Essential Tension. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Morrison, M. (1990), “Unification, Realism and Inference”, Unification, Realism and Inference 41:305332.Google Scholar
Morrison, M. (1998), “Modelling Nature: Between Physics and the Physical World”, Modelling Nature: Between Physics and the Physical World 38:6585.Google Scholar
Morrison, M. (1999), “Models as Autonomous Agents”, in Morgan, M. and Morrsion, M. (eds.), Models as Mediations: Essays in the Philosophy of the Natural and Social Sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 3865.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morrison, M. (2000), Unifying Scientific Theories: Physical Concepts and Mathematical Structures. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morrison, M. (forthcoming), “Theories as Representational Structures”, in Hartmann, Stephan, Hoefer, Carl, and Bovens, Luc (eds.), Nancy Cartwright's Philosophy of Science. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Redhead, M. (2001), “The Intelligibility of the Universe”, in O’Hear, A. (ed.), Philosophy and the New Millennium. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Smith, C., and Wise, N. (1989), Energy and Empire. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Steiner, M. (1999), The Applicability of Mathematics as a Philosophical Problem. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Suarez, M. (2003), “Scientific Representation: Against Similarity and Isomorphism”, Scientific Representation: Against Similarity and Isomorphism 17:225244.Google Scholar
Suppes, P. (1961), “A Comparison of the Meaning and Use of Models in the Mathematical and Empirical Sciences”, in Freudenthal, H. (ed.), The Concept and Role of the Model in Mathematics and Natural and Social Sciences. Dordrecht: Reidel, 163177.Google Scholar
Suppes, P. (1967), “What Is a Scientific Theory?”, in Morgenbesser, S. (ed.), Philosophy of Science Today. New York: Basic Books, 5567.Google Scholar
Suppes, P. (1974) “Recent Progress in Gauge Theories of Weak, Strong and Electromagnetic Interactions”, Recent Progress in Gauge Theories of Weak, Strong and Electromagnetic Interactions 46:255277.Google Scholar
Tarski, A. ([1935] 1956), “The Concept of Truth in Formalized Languages”, in Tarski, A., Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics: Papers from 1923 to 1938. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 152278.Google Scholar
Tarski, A. ([1936] 1956), “The Establishment of Scientific Semantics”, in Tarski, A., Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics: Papers from 1923 to 1938. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 401408.Google Scholar
Tarski, A. (1953), “A General Method in Proofs of Undecidability”, in Tarksi, A., Mostowski, A., and Robinson, R. M. (eds.), Undecidable Theories. Amsterdam: North-Holland.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B. (1980), The Scientific Image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Fraassen, B. (1985), “Empiricism and the Philosophy of Science”, in Churchland, P. and Hooker, C. (eds.), Images of Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 245308.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B. (1989), Laws and Symmetries. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Fraassen, B. (2002), Representation and Invariance of Scientific Structures. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
Weinberg, S. (1967), “A Model of Leptons”, A Model of Leptons 19:12641266.Google Scholar
Weyl, H. (1949), Philosophy of Mathematics and Natural Science. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Worrall, J. (1984), “An Unreal Image, Review of van Fraassen The Scientific Image”, An Unreal Image, Review of van Fraassen The Scientific Image 35:6580.Google Scholar