Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-c4f8m Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-23T14:50:21.176Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Kantian Eudaimonism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 September 2022

E. SONNY ELIZONDO*
Affiliation:
UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, SANTA BARBARA eselizondo@ucsb.edu

Abstract

My aim in this essay is to reorient our understanding of the Kantian ethical project, especially in relation to its assumed rivals. I do this by considering Kant's relation to eudaimonism, especially in its Aristotelian form. I argue for two points. First, once we understand what Kant and Aristotle mean by happiness, we can see that not only is it the case that, by Kant's lights, Aristotle is not a eudaimonist. We can also see that, by Aristotle's lights, Kant is a eudaimonist. Second, we can see that this agreement on eudaimonism actually reflects a deeper, more fundamental agreement on the nature of ethics as a distinctively practical philosophy. This is an important result, not just for the history of moral philosophy but for moral philosophy as well. For it suggests that both Kantians and Aristotelians may well have more argumentative resources available to them than is commonly thought.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the American Philosophical Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

This essay originated in an attempt to reconcile the ideas of two of my graduate teachers: Barbara Herman and Gavin Lawrence. I thank them both, knowing full well that they would find much to object to in my argument. For discussion of relevant issues, I also thank Patricio Fernandez, Tamar Schapiro, Jeanine Grenberg, Jeremy Fix, Ed Lamb, and several anonymous referees. Earlier versions of the essay were presented at the Central APA and Oxford Moral Philosophy Seminar. I thank the audiences at those occasions for useful discussion.

Although I quote from and cite modern editions and translations of Aristotle and Kant, for the specialist or those reading these sources in the original or other languages, I also provide, in brackets, the standard volume, section, or line numbers for these works. References to Aristotle employ the standard Bekker numbers. All references to Kant are to the volumes in Kants gesammelte Schriften and employ the standard Akadamie numbers with the following abbreviations: KpV (Critique of Practical Reason); KU (Critique of the Power of Judgment); KUEE (Critique of the Power of Judgment, First Introduction); G (Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals); MS (The Metaphysics of Morals); R (Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason).

References

Annas, Julia. (1993) The Morality of Happiness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Aristotle, . (1999) Nicomachean Ethics. Edited and translated by Irwin, T. H.. 2d ed. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Elizondo, E. Sonny. (2013) ‘Reason in its Practical Application’. Philosophers’ Imprint, 13, article 21. http://hdl.handle.net/2027/spo.3521354.0013.021.Google Scholar
Elizondo, E. Sonny. (2014) ‘More than a Feeling’. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 44, 425–42.10.1080/00455091.2014.959360CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elizondo, E. Sonny. (2016) ‘Morality is Its Own Reward’. Kantian Review, 21, 343–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Engstrom, Stephen. (1996) ‘Happiness and the Highest Good in Aristotle and Kant’. In Engstrom, Stephen and Whiting, Jennifer (eds.), Aristotle, Kant, and the Stoics: Rethinking Happiness and Duty (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 102–38.Google Scholar
Grenberg, Jeanine M. (2022) ‘Deontological Eudaimonism’. In Himmelmann, Beatrix and Serck-Hanssen, Camilla (eds.), The Court of Reason: Proceedings of the 13th International Kant Congress, vol. 3 (Berlin: De Gruyter), 1431–38.Google Scholar
Herman, Barbara. (1996) ‘Making Room for Character’. In Engstrom, Stephen and Whiting, Jennifer (eds.), Aristotle, Kant, and the Stoics: Rethinking Happiness and Duty (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 3660.Google Scholar
Holberg, Erica A. (2018) ‘Kant's Quasi-Eudaimonism’. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 56, 317–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Irwin, T. H. (1996) ‘Kant's Criticisms of Eudaimonism’. In Engstrom, Stephen and Whiting, Jennifer (eds.), Aristotle, Kant, and the Stoics: Rethinking Happiness and Duty (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 63101.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. (1996) The Metaphysics of Morals. Edited and translated by Gregor, Mary. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. (1997a) Critique of Practical Reason. Edited and translated by Gregor, Mary. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997a.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. (1997b) Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. Edited and translated by Gregor, Mary. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. (1998) Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason. Edited and translated by DiGiovanni, George and Wood, Allen W.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. (2000a) Critique of the Power of Judgment. Edited and translated by Guyer, Paul. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. (2000b) ‘First Introduction to the Critique of the Power of Judgment’. In Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgment. Edited and translated by Guyer, Paul (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 1–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine M. (1996) ‘From Duty and for the Sake of the Noble: Kant and Aristotle on Morally Good Action’. In Engstrom, Stephen and Whiting, Jennifer (eds.), Aristotle, Kant, and the Stoics: Rethinking Happiness and Duty (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 203–36.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine M. (2008) ‘Realism and Constructivism in Twentieth-Century Moral Philosophy’. In Korsgaard, The Constitution of Agency: Essays on Practical Reason and Moral Psychology (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 302–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine M. (2009) Self-Constitution: Agency, Identity, and Integrity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kraut, Richard. (1989) Aristotle and the Human Good. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lawrence, Gavin. (2004) ‘Reason, Intention and Choice: An Essay in Practical Philosophy’. In O'Hear, Anthony (ed.), Philosophy, Supplement No. 54: Modern Moral Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 265300.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lawrence, Gavin. (2006) ‘Human Good and Human Function’. In Kraut, Richard (ed.), Blackwell's Companion to Aristotle's Ethics (Oxford: Blackwell), 3775.Google Scholar
Lawrence, Gavin. (2009) ‘Is Aristotle's Function Argument Fallacious? Part I, Groundwork: Initial Clarification of Objections’. Philosophical Inquiry, 31, 191224.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDowell, John. (1980) ‘The Role of Eudaimonia in Aristotle's Ethics’. In Rorty, Amelie (ed.), Essays on Aristotle's Ethics (Berkeley: University of California Press), 359–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moore, G. E. (1993) Principia Ethica. 2d ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. (1999a) ‘Kantian Constructivism in Moral Theory’. In Rawls, Collected Papers (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 303–58.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. (1999b) ‘The Independence of Moral Theory’. In Rawls, Collected Papers (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 286302.Google Scholar
Sherman, Nancy. (1997) Making a Necessity of Virtue. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511624865CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sidgwick, Henry. (1981) The Methods of Ethics. 7th ed. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Whiting, Jennifer. (2006) ‘The Nicomachean Account of Philia’. In Kraut, Richard (ed.), Blackwell's Companion to Aristotle's Ethics (Oxford: Blackwell), 276304.Google Scholar
Wood, Allen W. (2000) ‘Kant vs. Eudaimonism’. In Cicovacki, Predrag (ed.), Kant's Legacy: Essays Dedicated to Lewis White Beck (Rochester: University of Rochester Press), 261–82.Google Scholar