Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-qsmjn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-25T06:03:01.030Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Signs of the Times: Kierkegaard's Diagnosis and Treatment of Hegelian Thought

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 April 2013

Clare Carlisle*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, University of Liverpool, Clare.Carlisle@liverpool.ac.uk
Get access

Abstract

In his 2003 book Kierkegaard's Relations to Hegel Reconsidered, Jon Stewart challenges the classical interpretation of Kierkegaard's response to Hegelian philosophy. Stewart convincingly argues that Kierkegaard's work addresses Danish Hegelians rather than Hegel himself. However, in my view the conclusion Stewart draws from this — that Kierkegaard's thought on the whole has much less to do with Hegel than earlier commentators have presumed — goes too far in undermining the philosophical and historical significance of Kierkegaard's work, and, perhaps more importantly, closes down too quickly the question of his relation to Hegelian philosophy. The following passage exemplifies Stewart's position:

Given that the two are doing quite different things, it is not clear why a comparison of their views is supposed to be fruitful in the first place … The presumption for Kierkegaard having made a philosophical criticism of Hegel is that [Kierkegaard] himself is a philosopher and shares with Hegel a certain common understanding of the nature and office of the discipline. A genuinely philosophical criticism would only make sense if there were a common basis of this kind. If, by contrast, Kierkegaard is not a philosopher in the same sense of the word, then it is not clear why he should be conceived as giving a philosophical criticism of Hegel. It seems rather that given the disparate nature of their respective projects, such a criticism would be at cross-purposes. (Stewart 2003: 636–37, emphasis in original)

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © The Hegel Society of Great Britain 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Carlisle, C. (2005), Kierkegaard's Philosophy of Becoming. Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Carlisle, C. (2009), ‘Ideals Without Idealism’ in Cornwell, J. and McGhee, M. (eds.), Philosophers and God. London: Continuum.Google Scholar
Carlisle, C. (2010), ‘Between Freedom and Necessity: Félix Ravaisson on habit and the moral life’, Inquiry 53:2:123145 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Deleuze, G. (2000), Proust and Signs, trans. Howard, R.. London: The Athlone Press.Google Scholar
Heiberg, J. L. (1833) Om Philosophiens Betydning for den nuvaerende Tid, Copenhagen.Google Scholar
Hegel, G. W. F. (1952), Hegel's Philosophy of Right, trans. Knox, T. M.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Inwood, M. (1992), A Hegel Dictionary. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Kierkegaard, S. (1978), Two Ages, trans. Hong, H. V. and Hong, E. H.. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Kierkegaard, S. (1980a), The Sickness Unto Death, trans. Hong, H. V. and Hong, E. H.. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Kierkegaard, S. (1980b), The Concept of Anxiety, trans. Thomte, R.. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Kierkegaard, S. (1982), The Corsair Affair, ed. and trans. Hong, H. V. and Hong, E. H.. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Kierkegaard, S. (1983), Fear and Trembling and Repetition, trans. Hong, H. V. and Hong, E. H.. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Kierkegaard, S. (1985), Philosophical Fragments, trans. Hong, H. V. and Hong, E. H.. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Kierkegaard, S. (1987), Either/Or, trans. Hong, H. V. and Hong, E. H.. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Kierkegaard, S. (1991), Practice in Christianity, trans. Hong, H. V. and Hong, E. H.. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Kierkegaard, S. (1992), Concluding Unscientific Postscript, trans. Hong, H. V. and Hong, E. H.. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Luther, M. (1972), Luther's Works, Volume 25: Lectures on Romans, ed. Oswald, H. C.. Saint Louis: Concordia.Google Scholar
Martensen, H. L. (1839), ‘Rationalisme, Supernaturalisme og principium exclusi medii i Anledning af H. H. Biskop Mynster Afhandling herom i dette Tidsskrifts forrige Hefte’, Tidsskrift for Litteratur og Kritik, 1.Google Scholar
Martensen, H. L. (1843), Den christelige Daab. Copenhagen.Google Scholar
Ravaisson, F. (2008), Of Habit, trans. Carlisle, C. and Sinclair, M.. London: Continuum.Google Scholar
Stewart, J. (2003), Kierkegaard's Relations to Hegel Reconsidered. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walsh, S. (2009), Thinking Christianly in an Existential Mode. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar