Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-m8qmq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-18T15:15:15.726Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Why Adolf Hitler Spared the Judges: Judicial Opposition Against the Nazi State

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 March 2019

Abstract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

The Nazi regime had loyal judges who willingly transformed the liberal German law into an instrument of oppression, discrimination and genocide. This was achieved without substantially interfering with the operation of the courts and without applying disciplinary measures on the judges. But, not all judges were congenial servants of the regime—some resisted in their capacity as judges. Based on case-studies and existing literature, this Article distinguishes between two different lines of judicial opposition to those in power: Between opposition taking place in the open and opposition in secret, and between opposition within what is accepted by those in power as being within the law and opposition that is in breach of the law. The Article then seeks to explain the deference the regime gave to judicial by employing institutional theory and the concept of path dependence. Germany was deeply embedded in the Western legal tradition of emphasis on law as an autonomous institution with an independent judiciary.

Type
The rule of law, constitutionalism and the judiciary
Copyright
Copyright © 2018 by German Law Journal, Inc. 

References

1 The Justice Case, in 3 Trials of War Criminals Before the Nuremberg Military Tribunals 50 (1951).Google Scholar

2 The Justice Case, supra note 1, at 51.Google Scholar

3 Ralph Angermund, Deutsche Richtershaft 1919–1945 255 (1990).Google Scholar

4 The Justice Case, supra note 1, at 31.Google Scholar

5 See most notably H.W.Koch, In the Name of the Volk Political Justice in Hitler‘s Germany (1989); Ingo Müller, Furchtbare Juristen Die unbewältigte Vergangenheit unserer Justiz, (1987) (Ger.), translated in Hitler‘s Justice: The Courts of the Third Reich (1991). For a treatment of military courts see Messerschmidt, Manfred, Was damals Recht war… NS-Militär- und Strafjustiz im Vernichtungskrieg (1996). See also the overview of the research by Ledford, Kenneth F., Judging German Judges in the Third Reich, in Steinweis, Alan E. & Rachlin, Robert D., The Law in Nazi Germany Ideology, Opportunism, and the Perversion of Justice 161–89 (2013).Google Scholar

6 See Loewenstein, Karl, Reconstruction of the Administration of Justice in the American Occupied Germany, 61 Harv. L. Rev. 419, 444 (1948): But not a single case is reported in which a judge who resigned was sent to a concentration camp, or even lost his pension. If he wished, he could leave the service and “sit the regime out” on his pension. Though such cases occurred not too frequently, they were known and widely commented on by the judiciary. Moreover—and this too was fully known—there were some judges, particularly among the older generation, who, neither resigning nor yielding, resisted pressure to the end. Nor is it correct to assume that non-party members among the judiciary were invariably denied promotion. No doubt one reason for this is that very few judges mounted any opposition against the regime. But some did quite openly without meeting with more serious sanctions than transfer to a different jurisdiction, lack of promotion or removal from office with a pension.Google Scholar

7 See Venema, Derk, The Judge, the Occupier, his Laws, and their Validity: Judicial Review by the Supreme Courts of Occupied Belgium, Norway, and the Netherlands 1940-1945 in the Context of their Professional Conduct and the Consequences for their Public Image, in Justice in Wartime and Revolutions: Europe 1795–1950 203, 209, 213 (M. de Koster & D. Heirbaut eds., 2012).Google Scholar

8 See Schorn, Hubert, Der Richter im Dritten Reich Gescichte und Dokumente (1959).Google Scholar

9 See Müller, supra note 5, at 200.Google Scholar

10 Michael Stolleis, The Law under the Swastika Studies on Legal History in Nazi Germany 151 (1988).Google Scholar

11 Joachim Perels & Wolfram Wette, Mit reinem Gewissen Wehrmachtrichter in der Bundesrepublik und ihre Opfer 16–7 (2011).Google Scholar

12 See Jörg Friedrich, Freispruch für die Nazi-Justiz Die Urteile gegen NS-Richter seit 1948 Eine Dokumentation (1983); Hans Petter Graver, Judges Against Justice: On Judges When the Rule of Law is Under Attack 143–57 (2015).Google Scholar

13 Studies of Nazism have at different times portrayed the German population as resistant to or complicit with the regime. See Kershaw, Ian, Preface to the Bloomsbury Revelations Edition, in The Nazi Dictatorship Problems and Perspectives of Interpretation (2015).Google Scholar

14 See generally Hoffman, Peter, History of the German Resistance, 1933–1945 (3d ed. 1996); Hans Mommsen, Alternatives to Hitler: German Resistance Under the Third Reich (2003); Nathan Stoltzfus, Hitler's Compromises: Coercion and Consensus in Nazi Germany (2016). See also Germans against Nazism: Nonconformity, Opposition and Resistance in the Third Reich: Essays in Honour of Peter Hoffmann (Nicosia, Francis R. & Stokes, Lawrence D. eds., 2015) (providing a comprehensive overview of the subject).Google Scholar

15 Mommsen, supra note 14, at 15.Google Scholar

16 See Bernd Rüthers, Verräter, Zufallshelden oder Gewissen der Nation? Facetten des Widerstandes in Deutschland (2008).Google Scholar

17 Heiko Maas, Furchtlose Juristen Richter und Staatsanwälte gegen das NS-Unrecht (2017).Google Scholar

18 See Mommsen, supra note 14, at 33.Google Scholar

19 See Schorn, supra note 8, at 50–2.Google Scholar

20 See Dworkin, Ronald, Law's Empire 105–07 (Harv. Univ. Press 1986).Google Scholar

21 See Raz, Joseph, The Authority of Law 330 (2d ed. 2009).Google Scholar

22 See Graver, Hans Petter, Judging without Impunity: On the Criminal Responsibility of Authoritarian Judges, 4 Bergen J. Crim. L. & Crim. Just. 1, 125–49 (2016).Google Scholar

23 Lothar Kreyssig, Aufsätze, Autobiographie under Dokumente 114 (Hans-Joachim Döring ed. 2011).Google Scholar

24 See id. at 115.Google Scholar

25 Raymond Wacks, Judges and Injustice, 101 S. African L. J. 266, 284 (1984).Google Scholar

26 See Venema, supra note 7, at 218.Google Scholar

27 See T Mahmud T, Jurisprudence of Successful Treason: Coup d'Etat and Common Law, 27 Cornell Int'l L. J. 27 49, 124 (1994).Google Scholar

28 The Truth and Reconciliation Commission and the Bench, Legal Practitioners and Legal Academics—Written Presentations, 115 S. African L.J. 15, 45 (1998).Google Scholar

29 See Terence c. Halliday, Lucien Karpik, & Malcolm m. Feeley, Fighting for Political Freedom: Comparative Studies of the Legal Complex and Political Liberalism (2007).Google Scholar

30 See Jeffrey Brand-Ballard, Limits of legality The Ethics of Lawless Judging (2010) (providing a brilliant and convincing argument on the subject).Google Scholar

31 See Graver, supra note 22.Google Scholar

32 100. Geburtstag von Hans von Dohnanyi: Ansprache des Präsidenten des Bundesgerichtshofs Prof. Dr. Günter Hirsch beim Festakt aus Anlaß des 100. Gubertstags von Hans von Dohnanyi am. März 200, Der Bundesgerichtshof, http://www.bundesgerichtshof.de/DE/DasGericht/Praesidenten/Hirsch/HirschReden/rede08032002.html (last visited March 8, 2002).Google Scholar

33 See Venema, supra note 7, at 218.Google Scholar

34 See Buchheit, Gert, Richter in roter Robe: Freisler, Präsident des Volksgerichtshofes, 27–9 (1968).Google Scholar

35 Hans Bergemann & Simone Ladwig-Winters, Jüdische Richter am Kammergericht nach 1933—Eine Dokumentation 27 (2005).Google Scholar

36 See Graver, supra note 12, at 98–101.Google Scholar

37 See Maas, supra note 17, at 245–64.Google Scholar

38 See Wachsmann, Nikolaus, KL: a History of the Nazi Concentration Camps 8693 (2015).Google Scholar

39 See Schorn, supra note 8, at 404–08.Google Scholar

40 Wilhelm Niemöller, Macht geht vor Recht Der PROZEß Martin Niemöllers 83 (1952).Google Scholar

41 See Graver, supra note 12, at 60–8 (reporting the mainstream adaptation of Nazi Anti-Semitism into judicial practice).Google Scholar

42 See Maas, supra note 17.Google Scholar

43 See Maas, supra note 17, at 43–53.Google Scholar

44 See Maas, supra note 17, at 199–212.Google Scholar

45 See Maas, supra note 17, at 238.Google Scholar

46 See Schorn, supra note 8, at 649–52 (providing the relevant description of the case); see also The Justice Case, supra note 1, at 530–32 (providing the Reich Ministry of Justice's translation of the case).Google Scholar

47 The Justice Case, supra note 1, at 531.Google Scholar

49 The presentation of Konrad Morgan and his activities is based on the book by Herlinde Pauer-Studer & David Velleman, Konrad Morgen: The Conscience of a Nazi Judge (2015).Google Scholar

50 See Pauer-Studer, supra note 49, at 41.Google Scholar

51 See id. at xi.Google Scholar

52 One Hundred and Ninety-Eighth Day: Thursday; 8 August 1946, in Nuremberg Trial Proceedings Volume 20, http://avalon.law.yale.edu/imt/08-08-46.asp.Google Scholar

53 See Pauer-Studer, supra note 49, at 89.Google Scholar

54 One Hundred and Ninety-Eighth Day: Thursday; 8 August 1946, supra note 52.Google Scholar

55 See Pauer-Studer, supra note 49, at 95.Google Scholar

56 An alternative hypothesis might be as follows. After the war, and after learning about the world's reaction to the holocaust, Morgen realized the moral implications of what he had been involved with, or at least he understood the reaction of the rest of the world. At the same time, an important witness implicated him directly in the deportation of Jews from Hungary. He was in American custody and as an SS judge he belonged to the class II, possibly even class I, of offenders on the list of the allies. This would mean that he may have had a real fear of being brought to trial and receiving a severe sentence. To counteract this, he started portraying himself as a resister of the mass killings. Although he was denounced in the early days after the defeat, he was protected by the solidarity of the old network as time passed. This is quite in line with the general experiences. To elaborate: But here enters a socio-psychological element which AMG (American Military Government) was unable to neutralize—the class solidarity of the judiciary, which, subconsciously or consciously, began to balance and outweigh the desire for political cleanliness. In fact, under the impact of the occupation, a certain national solidarity has emerged—not merely in the civil service but among all classes—which tries to save as many colleagues as possible from the clutches of the denazification beast.Google Scholar

Karl Lowenstein (Reconstruction of the Administration of Justice in American-Occupied Germany, 61 Harv. L. Rev. 419, 449 (1948). This illustrates the methodological difficulties present in most of the cases when investigating into instances of resistance. In many cases those that try to resist have to keep this secret in order to be effective and to protect themselves. This counts for a scarcity of sources. At the same time, many may have motives to paint themselves in a better light after the end of an authoritarian regime in order to escape criticism. This puts both the validity and the reliability of sources in doubt.Google Scholar

57 See Bohn, Robert, Reichskommissariat Norwegen: “Nationalsozialistische Neuordning” und Kriegswirtschaft 92 (2000).Google Scholar

58 See Norsk Retstidende [Norwegian Court Reports] 468 (1947); Norsk Retstidende [Norwegian Court Reports] 1088 (1948).Google Scholar

59 See Massnahmen und Bemühungen des Gerichts, um die scharfen Tendenzen Terbovens und Rediess zu mildern, Oslo, Akershus (Dec. 4, 1945) (on file in L-sak Oslo politikammer, dom 4028–2030: Latza, Regis, Kehr mfl).Google Scholar

60 The US Military Tribunal in the case against leaders of the German judicial system expressed an opinion along the same line in saying: The limitations on freedom of speech which were imposed in the enforcement of these laws are revolting to our sense of justice. A court would have no hesitation in condemning them under any free constitution, including that of the Weimar Republic, if the limitations were applied in time of peace; but even under the protection of the Constitution of the United States a citizen is not wholly free to attack the Government or to interfere with its military aims in time of war. In the face of a real and present danger, freedom of speech may be somewhat restricted even in America. Can we then say that in the throes of total war and in the presence of impending disaster those officials who enforced these savage laws in a last desperate effort to stave off defeat were guilty of crimes against humanity?Google Scholar

See Case, The Justice, supra note 1, at 1026. See also the line of reasoning by the famous US Justice Oliver Wendel Holmes in the well-known case on forced sterilization, where he states: We have seen more than once that the public welfare may call upon the best citizens for their lives. It would be strange if it could not call upon those who already sap the strength of the State for these lesser sacrifices, often not felt to be such by those concerned, in order to prevent our being swamped with incompetence.Google Scholar

Buck v. Bell, 274 U.S. 200 (1927).Google Scholar

61 Massnahmen und Bemühungen des Gerichts, supra note 59um die scharfen Tendenzen Terbovens und Rediess' zu mildern, Oslo, Akershus, supra note 59.Google Scholar

62 Such an exchange of information had been established in 1939 between the Volksgerichtshof and the Gestapo in Berlin. See Koch, supra note 5, at 87.Google Scholar

63 Ernst Kanter, Erlebnisse als Chefrichter in Dänemark Februar 1943–Mai 1945 (Signatur ZS 1991) 1 Institut für Zeitgeschichte München-Berlin Archiv (1991).Google Scholar

64 See Kershaw, supra note 13, at 240.Google Scholar

65 See Halliday, supra note 29, at 6–9 (providing a description of the concept of a legal complex).Google Scholar

66 See Graver, supra note 22.Google Scholar

67 See Graver, supra note 12, at 41–5Google Scholar

68 See Hoffman, supra note 14, at 20.Google Scholar

69 See Schorn, supra note 8, at 315.Google Scholar

70 Law Reports of Trials of War Criminals vol. XIV, United Nations War Crimes Commission 646 (1949) (reporting on what is known as the Ministries Case).Google Scholar

71 Hannah Arendt, Responsibility and Judgement 35 (2003).Google Scholar

72 See Maas, supra note 17, at 55.Google Scholar

73 See Pauer-Studer, supra note 49, at 120–27.Google Scholar

74 See Helmke, Gretchen, Courts under Constraints Judges, Generals and Presidents in Argentina 21 (2004).Google Scholar

75 See Manfred Görtemaker & Christoph Safferling, Die Akte Rosenburg Das Bundesministerium der Justiz und die NS-Zeit 143 (2016).Google Scholar

76 See Schorn, supra note 8.Google Scholar

77 See Trial of the Major War Criminals before the International Military Tribunal: Nuremberg 14 November 1945—1 October 1946 416, 429–30 (1947) (providing the testimony of Günther Reinecke before the International Military Tribunal in Nuremberg on August 6, 1945).Google Scholar

78 See to the act and the letter from the office of the Fuhrer to the Ministry of Justice, Ekkehard Reitter, Franz Gürtner, Politische Biographie eines deutschen Juristen 1881–1941, 192193 (1976).Google Scholar

79 See Maas supra note 17, at 176.Google Scholar

80 Anke Silomon, Lothar Kreyssig—Realistischer Visionär, Prophet und Schwärmer, in Kothar Krezssig Ausätze, Autobiographie und Dokumente, Evangelische Verlagsanstalt Leipzig 19 (Hans Joachim Döring ed., 2011).Google Scholar

81 Lothar Gruchmann, Ein unbequemer Amtsrichter im Dritten Reich, in Kothar Krezssig Ausätze, Autobiographie und Dokumente 41 (Hans Joachim Döring ed., 2011).Google Scholar

82 The letter and other documents from his file in the Ministry of Justice are printed in Döring (ed.) 2011 pp. 143 ff.Google Scholar

83 Stoltzfus claims that Adolf Hitler pardoned Kreyssig, “instead of following the will of other government agencies to exact punishment.” Stoltzfus, supra note 14, at 20, 76. Nevertheless, in March 1942, Hitler approved the recommendation by the Ministry of Justice of May 10, 1941, to dismiss Kreyssig from his position with pension rights. See Gruchmann, supra note 81, at 47.Google Scholar

84 See Stoltzfus supra note 14, at 271.Google Scholar

85 See Graver, Hans Petter, Judicial Independence Under Authoritarian Rule: An Institutional Approach to the Legal Tradition of the West, Rule, Hague J. L. (2018).Google Scholar

86 See Berman, Harold J., Law and Revolution: The Formation of the Western Legal Tradition 910 (1983).Google Scholar

87 Douglass c. North, The Paradox of the West 107 (Stanford Univ. Press 1991); Francis Fukuyama, The Origins of Political Order From Prehuman Times to the French Revolution 246 (Farrar, Straus & Giroux ed. 2011).Google Scholar

88 See Koch, supra note 5, at 104–07 (describing the battle in 1941 between the Ministry and Richard Heidrich over the respect of the statutes of the Volksgerichtshof).Google Scholar

89 See Buchheit, supra note 34 at 46–54.Google Scholar

90 Kanter, supra note 63.Google Scholar

91 See Pauer-Studer, supra note 49, at 41.Google Scholar

92 The government in Nazi Germany has been characterized as “chaotic in structure.” See Kershaw, supra note 13, at 94.Google Scholar

93 See Legislating the Holocaust: the Bernhard Loesener Memoirs and Supporting Documents (Karl Schleunes ed., 2001).Google Scholar

94 See the discussion between Natan Stoltzfuss and Wolf Gruner over the demonstrations by German wives of 1,700 Jewish husbands in Rosenstrasse in February 1943 in American Historical Review 2007 pp 1628–1629.Google Scholar

95 See Reitter supra note 78, at 147.Google Scholar

96 See id. at 201–07. See also Koch, supra note 5, at 87.Google Scholar

97 See Fraenkel, Ernst, The Dual State a Contribution to the Theory of Dictatorship (2006).Google Scholar

98 See Meierhenrich, Jens, The Remnants of the Rechtsstaat An Ethnography of Nazi Law (2018).Google Scholar

99 Douglass c. North, Understanding the Process of Economic Change 51 (2005).Google Scholar

100 See id. at 77.Google Scholar

101 Id. at 83.Google Scholar

102 See Bourdieu, Pierre, Outline of a Theory of Practice 72 (1977).Google Scholar

103 Id. at 78.Google Scholar

104 See Buchheit, supra note 34, at 49.Google Scholar

105 See Linder, Marc, The Supreme Labor Court in Nazi Germany: a Jurisprudencial Analysis, 15 (1987).Google Scholar

106 Detlev Garbe, Im Namen des Volkes?! Die Rechtlichen Grundlagen der Militärjustiz im NS-Staat und ihre „Bewältigung“nach 1945 in Erinnerungsarbeit Grundlage einer Kultur des Friedens, (Nolz, Bernhard und Popp, Wolfgang Hrsg. 2000), 100 (my translation from German).Google Scholar

107 See Reitter, supra note 78, at 177–80.Google Scholar

108 See Fraenkel, Ernst, The Dual State a Contribution to the Theory of Dictatorship (1941).Google Scholar

109 This is not to say that their approach to law was positivist and that legal positivism can explain the conformity of the German judiciary with the demands and interests of the Nazi rulers. Nevertheless, the famous article of Gustav Radbruch in which he proposed legal positivism as the factor that could account for the atrocities of the German judiciary quickly established itself as a convenient exculpating explanation. For an overview see for an overview Paulson, Stanley L., Lon L. Fuller, Gustav Radbruch, and the “Positivist” Theses, 13 L. & Philosophy 313 (1994). The positivism thesis also established itself within academic literature on the history of Nazi Germany. See for instance Koch 1997 p. 247. It has, however, been solidly refuted after careful studies of official and legal material of the time. See, e.g., Bernd Rüthers, Die unbegrenzte Auslegung, Mohr Siebeck Tübingen 1968 (7th ed. 2012); Herlinde PauerStuder & Julian Fink, Rechtfertigungen des Unrechts Das Rechtsdenken im Nationalsozialismus in Orginaltexten (Surkamp Berlin 2014). One reason why a positivism explanation may seem compelling is that it may be confused with psychological factors that place obedience with authority. The German judges were obedient, but this does not entail that the predominant legal theory and method were positivist. See Graver, supra note 12, at 239–51.Google Scholar