Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-qxdb6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-27T22:50:19.960Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Perniciousness of Higher-Order Evidence on Aesthetic Appreciation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 June 2023

David Sackris*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Arapahoe Community College, Littleton, CO, USA
Rasmus Rosenberg Larsen
Affiliation:
Department of Forensic Psychology, University of Toronto Mississauga, Mississauga, ON, Canada
*
Corresponding author. Email: david.sackris@gmail.com

Abstract

We demonstrate that many philosophers accept the following claim: When an aesthetic object is apprehended correctly, taking pleasure in said object is a reliable sign that the object is aesthetically successful. We undermine this position by showing that what grounds our pleasurable experience is opaque: In many cases, the experienced pleasure is attributable to factors that have little to do with the aesthetic object. The evidence appealed to is a form of Higher-Order Evidence (HOE) and we consider attempts to overcome said evidence. We argue they are unsuccessful. We conclude by considering what this means for our practice of making aesthetic judgements.

Résumé

Résumé

Nous démontrons que de nombreux philosophes acceptent l'affirmation suivante : lorsqu'un objet esthétique est appréhendé correctement, prendre plaisir à cet objet est un signe fiable que l'objet est esthétiquement réussi. Nous minons cette position en montrant que les bases sur lesquelles repose notre expérience de plaisir sont opaques : dans de nombreux cas, le plaisir éprouvé est attribuable à des facteurs qui n'ont que peu à voir avec l'objet esthétique. La preuve invoquée est une forme de preuve d'ordre supérieur et nous considérons les tentatives de surmonter ladite preuve. Nous soutenons que ces tentatives sont infructueuses. Nous concluons en examinant ce que cela signifie pour notre pratique du jugement esthétique.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the Canadian Philosophical Association / Publié par Cambridge University Press au nom de l’Association canadienne de philosophie.

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Bach, K. (2013). Review: Burnham, Douglas and Skilleås, Ole Martin. The aesthetics of wine. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 71(4), 388389. https://doi.org/10.1111/jaac.12037_4CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boeck, W., & Sabartés, J. (1955). Picasso. Henry N. Abrams, Inc.Google Scholar
Brochet, F. (2001). Chemical object representation in the field of consciousness. Grand Prix of the Académie Amorim. https://www.cervejaetremoco.pt/a-fragilidade-da-percepcao-do-gosto/brochet_wine_experiment.pdfGoogle Scholar
Budd, M. (1999). Aesthetic judgements, aesthetic principles, and aesthetic properties. European Journal of Philosophy, 7(3), 295311. https://doi.org/10.1111/1468-0378.00090CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burnham, D., & Skilleås, O. (2012). The aesthetics of wine. Wiley.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burnham, D., & Skilleås, O. (2014). Categories and appreciation — A reply to Sackris. Journal of Value Inquiry, 48(3), 551557. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10790-014-9441-1Google Scholar
Carlson, A. (1981). Nature, aesthetic judgment, and objectivity. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 40(1), 1528. https://doi.org/10.2307/430349CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Christensen, D. (2010). Higher-order evidence. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 81(1), 185215. https://10.1111/j.1933-1592.2010.00366.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cutting, J. (2003). Gustave Caillebotte, French impressionism, and mere exposure. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review, 10(2), 319343. https://doi.org/10.3758/bf03196493CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Davies, S. (2006). Aesthetic judgements, artworks and functional beauty. The Philosophical Quarterly, 56(223), 224241. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9213.2006.00439.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dolnick, E. (2008). The forger's spell: A true story of Vermeer, Nazis, and the greatest art hoax of the twentieth century. Harper.Google Scholar
Dorsch, F. (2014). The limits of aesthetic empiricism. In Currie, G., Kieran, M., Meskin, A., & Robson, J. (Eds.), Aesthetics and the sciences of mind (pp. 75100). Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199669639.003.0005CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feldman, R. (2009). Evidentialism, higher-order evidence, and disagreement. Episteme, 6(3), 294312. https://doi.org/10.3366/e1742360009000720CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Flexas, A., Rosselló, J., Christensen, J. F., Nadal, M., Olivera La Rosa, A., & Munar, E. (2013). Affective priming using facial expressions modulates liking for abstract art. PLoS ONE, 8(11), e80154. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0080154CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Friend, S. (2014). Walton, Kendall. In Kelly, M. (Ed.), Encyclopedia of aesthetics (2nd edition). Oxford University Press. https://www.oxfordreference.com/display/10.1093/acref/9780199747108.001.0001/acref-9780199747108-e-747?rskey=gS2IP8&result=753Google Scholar
Gorodeisky, K., & Marcus, E. (2018). Aesthetic rationality. Journal of Philosophy, 115(3), 113140. https://doi.org/10.5840/jphil201811538CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hartke, K. (2017). “The Sideways effect”: How a wine-obsessed film reshaped the industry. National Public Radio. https://www.npr.org/sections/thesalt/2017/07/05/535038513/the-sideways-effect-how-a-wine-obsessed-film-reshaped-the-industryGoogle Scholar
Hume, D. (1985). Of the standard of taste. In Miller, E. (Ed.), Essays moral, political, and literary (pp. 226249). Liberty Classics.Google Scholar
Kieran, M. (2010). The vice of snobbery: Aesthetic knowledge, justification and virtue in art appreciation. Philosophical Quarterly, 60(239), 243263. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9213.2009.615.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kieran, M. (2011). The fragility of aesthetic knowledge: Aesthetic psychology and appreciative virtues. In Schellekens, E. & Goldie, P. (Eds.), The aesthetic mind: Philosophy and psychology (pp. 3243). Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199691517.003.0003CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kivy, P. (2015). De gustibus: Arguing about taste and why we do it. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Larsen, R. R., & Sackris, D. (2020). Feeling the aesthetic: A pluralist sentimentalist theory of aesthetic experience. Estetika: The European Journal of Aesthetics, 57(2), 116134. https://doi.org/10.33134/eeja.212Google Scholar
Lasonen-Aarnio, M. (2014). Higher-order evidence and the limits of defeat. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 88(2), 314345. https://doi.org/10.1111/phpr.12090CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levinson, J. (1980). What a musical work is. Journal of Philosophy, 77(1), 528. https://doi.org/10.2307/2025596CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levinson, J. (2002). Hume's standard of taste: The real problem. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 60(3), 227238. https://doi.org/10.1111/1540-6245.00070CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levinson, J. (2010). Artistic worth and personal taste. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 68(3), 225233. https://www.jstor.org/stable/40793264Google Scholar
Lin, L., Hoegg, J., & Aquino, K. (2018). When beauty backfires: The effects of server attractiveness on consumer taste perceptions. Journal of Retailing, 94(3), 296311. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jretai.2018.04.003CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lopes, D. M. (2018). Being for beauty: Aesthetic agency and value. Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198827214.001.0001Google Scholar
Lukacs, P. (2013). Inventing wine: A new history of one of the world's most ancient pleasures. W. W. Norton.Google Scholar
Malfeito-Ferreira, M. (2021). Fine wine flavour perception and appreciation: Blending neuronal processes, tasting methods and expertise. Trends in Food Science & Technology, 115, 332346. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tifs.2021.06.053CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meskin, A., Phelan, M., Moore, M., & Kieran, M. (2013). Mere exposure to bad art. British Journal of Aesthetics, 53(2), 139164. https://doi.org/10.1093/aesthj/ays060CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meskin, A., Robson, J., Ichino, A., Goffin, K., & Monseré, A. (2018). Philosophical aesthetics and cognitive science. WIREs Cognitive Science, 9(1), 115. https://doi.org/10.1002/wcs.1445CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Nanay, B. (2017). Perceptual learning, the mere exposure effect and aesthetic anti-realism. Leonardo, 50(1), 5863.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Naukkarinen, O., & Bragge, J. (2016). Aesthetics in the age of digital humanities. Journal of Aesthetics & Culture, 8(1), 30072. https://doi.org/10.3402/jac.v8.30072CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Olsen, S. H. (2014). Aesthetic appreciation. In Kelly, M. (Ed.), Encyclopedia of aesthetics (2nd edition). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Payne, A. (Director) (2004). Sideways (film). Searchlight Pictures.Google Scholar
Plassmann, H., O'Doherty, J., Shiv, B., & Rangel, A. (2008). Marketing actions can modulate neural representations of experienced pleasantness. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America , 105(3), 10501054. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.0706929105CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Prinz, J. (2011). Emotion and aesthetic value. In Schellekens, E. & Goldie, P. (Eds.), The aesthetic mind (pp. 7188). Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199691517.003.0006Google Scholar
Robinson, J. (1997). Confessions of a wine lover. Penguin.Google Scholar
Robson, J. (2018). Aesthetic testimony and the test of time. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 96(3), 729748. https://doi.org/10.1111/phpr.12363CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sackris, D. (2018). What Jancis Robinson didn't know may have helped her. Erkenntnis, 84(4), 805822. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-018-9981-zCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sackris, D. (2020). The arbitrariness of aesthetic judgment. Journal of Value Inquiry, 55(4), 625646. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10790-020-09759-wCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salganik, M. J., Dodds, P. S., & Watts, D. J. (2006). Experimental study of inequality and unpredictability in an artificial cultural market. Science, 311(5762), 854856. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1121066CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salganik, M. J., & Watts, D. J. (2009). Web-based experiments for the study of collective social dynamics in cultural markets. Topics in Cognitive Science, 1(3), 439468. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1756-8765.2009.01030.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scruton, R. (2009). I drink therefore I am. Continuum.Google Scholar
Smith, B. C. (2007). The objectivity of tastes and tasting. In Smith, B. C. (Ed.), Questions of taste: The philosophy of wine (pp. 4178). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Tabor, G. M. (2006). The judgment of Paris. Simon and Schuster.Google Scholar
Tal, E. (2021). Is higher-order evidence evidence? Philosophical Studies, 178(10), pp. 31573175. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-020-01574-0CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Todd, C. (2011). The philosophy of wine: A case of truth, beauty and intoxication. Queen's University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/upo9781844654819CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walton, K. (1970). Categories of art. Philosophical Review, 79(3), pp. 334367.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wansink, B., Payne, C. R., & North, J. (2007). Fine as North Dakota wine: Sensory expectations and the intake of companion foods. Psychology and Behavior, 90(5), 712716. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.physbeh.2006.12.010Google Scholar
Warncke, C. P., & Walther, I. E. (2006). Picasso. Taschen.Google Scholar
Werness, H. (1983). Hans van Meegeren fecit. In Dutton, D. (Ed.), The forger's art: Forgery and the philosophy of art (pp. 157). University of California Press.Google Scholar
Whiting, D. (2019). Whither higher-order evidence? In Skipper, M. & Steglich-Petersen, A. (Eds.), Higher-order evidence: New essays (pp. 246264). Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198829775.003.0012CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whiting, D. (2020). Higher-order evidence. Analysis, 80(4), pp. 789807. https://doi.org/10.1093/analys/anaa056CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zajonc, R. B. (1968). Attitudinal effects of mere exposure. Journal of Psychology and Social Psychology, 9(2), 127. https://doi.org/10.1037/h0025848Google Scholar
Zajonc, R. B. (1980). Feeling and thinking: Preferences need no inference. American Psychologist, 35(2), 151175. https://doi.org/10.1037/0003-066x.35.2.151CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zangwill, N. (2001). Hume, taste, and teleology. In Zangwill, N. (Ed.), The metaphysics of beauty (pp. 149165). Cornell University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zangwill, N. (2021). Aesthetic judgment. In Zalta, E. N. (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2021/entries/aesthetic-judgment/Google Scholar