Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-dnltx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-24T15:39:45.657Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Needs and Rights

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  13 April 2010

L. Duane Willard
Affiliation:
University of Nebraska at Omaha

Extract

It is not difficult to sympathize with the strong impulse among philosophers to attempt to explain, justify, and even define moral concepts in factual terms. For without some kind of grounding in the facts of human nature, we may be quite perplexed concerning what relevance moral concepts have to our actual decisions, actions, and social relationships. Put another way, without grounding moral concepts in facts we may be quite puzzled as to the connections between principles and practice, between the ideal and the actual. The history of ethical theory contains several serious efforts by various philosophers to provide factual grounding for moral concepts, efforts which we cannot here take up.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Philosophical Association 1987

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 For example: Handy, Rollo, “A Need Definition of 'Value'”, The Philosophical Quarterly 10 (1960), 156163;CrossRefGoogle ScholarMcCall, Storrs, “Human Needs and the Quality of Life”, in King-Farlow, John and Shea, William R., eds., Values and the Quality of Life (New York: Science History Publications, 1976)Google Scholar; Nielsen, Kai, “Morality and Needs”, in MacIntosh, J. J. and Coval, S., eds., The Business of Reason (New York: Humanities Press, 1969)Google Scholar; Peffer, Rodney, “A Defense of Rights to Well-being”, Philosophy and Public-Affairs 8 (1978), 6587;Google ScholarTranøy, K. E., “'Ought' Implies 'Can': A Bridge from Fact to Norm?”, Part 2, Ratio 17 (1975), 147175;Google Scholar and, Wollheim, Richard, “Needs, Desires and Moral Turpitude”, in Peters, R. S., ed., Nature and Conduct (London: Macmillan Press, 1975)Google Scholar.

2 Ingram, Peter, “Natural Rights: A Reappraisal”, Journal of Value Inquiry 15 (1981), 318.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

3 Ibid., 13.

4 Ibid., 15.

6 Ibid., 10–11.

7 Ibid., 13.

8 Louch, A. R., Explanation and Human Action (Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1966), 78.Google Scholar

9 White, Alan R., Modal Thinking (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1975), 117118.Google Scholar

10 Willard, L. Duane, “Needs and Medicine”, Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 7 (1982), 259274;CrossRefGoogle Scholar and Needs and Business”, Westminster Institute Review 2 (1982), 710.Google Scholar

11 Phillips, D. Z. and Mounce, H. O., “On Morality's Having a Point”, Philosophy 40 (1965), 308319.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

12 McCloskey, H. J., “Human Needs, Rights, and Political Values”, American Philosophical Quarterly 13 (1976), 1.Google Scholar

13 Tranøy, , “'Ought' Implies 'Can'”, 149, 153, 154.Google Scholar

14 Ingram, , “Natural Rights”, 89.Google Scholar

15 Ibid., 5.

16 White, , Modal Thinking, 110.Google Scholar

17 Hudson, W. D., Modern Moral Philosophy (Garden City, NY: Doubleday, 1970), 317318.Google Scholar

18 , McCloskey, “Human Needs, Rights”, 2. See also Thomson, Judith Jarvis, “A Defense of Abortion”, Philosophy and Public Affairs 1 (1971), 55.Google Scholar

19 Ingram, , “Natural Rights”, 4.Google Scholar

20 Ibid., 5.