Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-8zxtt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-12T02:46:11.829Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Leibniz's Moral Psychology of an Evil Person

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  17 November 2023

Evelyn Vargas*
Affiliation:
Departamento de filosofía, Universidad Nacional de La Plata, IDHICS (UNLP-CONICET), Argentina
Markku Roinila
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, History and Art studies, University of Helsinki, Finland
*
Corresponding author: Evelyn Vargas; Email: evelyn.vargas@gmail.com

Abstract

Our focus in this article concerns Leibniz's views on evil. Our goal is to examine which are the consequences of his conception of moral agency for the moral psychology of the genuinely evil person. For Leibniz, moral failure is an epistemic error since it involves some false practical judgement. Moral maxims may be represented in blind or symbolic cognitions, but then moral agents can misrepresent the evil consequences of their behaviour. Finally, we discuss Leibniz's view on habits that may help virtuous persons strive for perfection but also enable evil persons to continue sinning.

Résumé

Résumé

Dans cet article, nous nous concentrons sur les vues de Leibniz à propos du mal. Notre objectif est d'examiner quelles sont les conséquences de sa conception de l'agence morale pour la psychologie morale de la personne véritablement mauvaise. Pour Leibniz, le mal moral est une erreur épistémique puisqu'il implique un faux jugement pratique. Les maximes morales peuvent être représentées par des cognitions aveugles ou symboliques, et par conséquent, un agent moral peut se tromper dans sa représentation des conséquences mauvaises de ses décisions. Enfin, nous discutons de la perspective de Leibniz sur les habitudes qui peuvent aider les personnes vertueuses à rechercher la perfection, mais aussi permettre aux personnes mauvaises de continuer à pécher.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the Canadian Philosophical Association / Publié par Cambridge University Press au nom de l’Association canadienne de philosophie.

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Alston, W. P. (1988). The deontological conception of epistemic justification. Philosophical Perspectives, 2, 257299. https://doi.org/10.2307/2214077CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bayle, P. (1704). Reponse aux questions d'un provincial. Leers. https://archive.org/details/reponseauxquesti0102baylGoogle Scholar
Brown, G. (1995). Leibniz's moral philosophy. In Jolley, N. (Ed.), The Cambridge companion to Leibniz (pp. 411441). Cambridge University Press. https://www.cambridge.org/core/books/cambridge-companion-to-leibniz/72E25B87717845B2D09CFD2CE45AF63EGoogle Scholar
Brown, G. (2011). Disinterested love: Understanding Leibniz's reconciliation of self- and other-regarding motives. British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 19(2), 265303. https://doi.org/10.1080/09608788.2011.555162CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, G. (2018). Happiness and justice. In Antognazza, M. R. (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of Leibniz (pp. 623640). Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199744725.013.37Google Scholar
Carlin, L. (2002). Reward and punishment in the best possible world: Leibniz's theory of natural retribution. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 40(2), 139160. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.2041-6962.2002.tb01894.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, J. D. (2005). Video meliora proboque, deteriora sequor: Leibniz on the intellectual source of sin. In Rutherford, D. & Cover, J. A. (Eds.), Leibniz: Nature and freedom (pp. 234252). Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/0195143744.003.0013CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frey, J. (2016). Was Leibniz an egoist? Journal of the History of Philosophy, 54(4), 601624. https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2016.0072CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griard, J. (2007). Leibniz's social quasi-contract. British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 15(3), 513533. https://doi.org/10.1080/09608780701444956CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heinekamp, A. (1969). Das Problem des Guten bei Leibniz. Bouvier.Google Scholar
Hieronymi, P. (2006). Controlling attitudes. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 87(1), 4574. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0114.2006.00247.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Imlay, R. A. (2002). Leibniz on freedom of the will: A vindication. Studia Leibnitiana, 34(1), 8190. https://www.jstor.org/stable/40694408Google Scholar
Jolley, N. (2005). Leibniz. Routledge. https://doi.org/10.4324/9780203088135Google Scholar
Jorati, J. (2017). Leibniz on causation and agency. Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108131629CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jorati, J. (2021). The guise of the good in Leibniz. Philosophical Explorations, 24(1), 4862. https://doi.org/10.1080/13869795.2020.1868114CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leibniz, G. W. (1923–). Sämtliche Schriften und Briefe, Reihe I–VIII. Berlin-Brandenburgische Akademie der Wissenschaften & Akademie der Wissenschaften in Göttingen. De Gruyter. https://www.degruyter.com/serial/lsb-b/html?lang=de#volumes (A)Google Scholar
Leibniz, G. W. (1965). Die philosophischen Schriften, I–VII (C. I. Gerhardt, Ed.). Olms. https://www.olms.de/search/Detail.aspx?pr=2002803 (Original work published 1875–1890.) (GP)Google Scholar
Leibniz, G. W. (1969). Philosophical papers and letters: A selection (2nd ed., Loemker, L. E., Ed.). Reidel. https://link.springer.com/book/10.1007/978-94-010-1426-7 (L)Google Scholar
Leibniz, G. W. (1988). Political writings (2nd ed., Riley, P., Ed.). Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511810084 (R)Google Scholar
Leibniz, G. W. (1989). Philosophical essays (Ariew, R. & Garber, D., Eds. & Trans.). Hackett. https://hackettpublishing.com/philosophy/modern-philosophy/philosophical-essays (AG)Google Scholar
Leibniz, G. W. (1990). Opera omnia (Dutens, L., Ed.). Olms. https://www.olms.de/search/Detail.aspx?pr=4799 (Original work published 1768.) (D)Google Scholar
Leibniz, G. W. (1996). Theodicy: Essays on the goodness of God, the freedom of man, and the origin of evil (Farrer, A., Ed., Huggard, E. M., Trans.). Open Court. https://archive.org/details/theodicyessayson0000leib (Originally published by Routledge, 1951.) (H)Google Scholar
Leibniz, G. W. (1996). New essays on human understanding (Remnant, P. & Bennett, J., Eds. & Trans.). Cambridge University Press. https://www.cambridge.org/core/books/leibniz-new-essays-on-human-understanding/0E436EC396C5F68361E054626569B284 (RB)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leibniz, G. W. (2005). Confessio philosophi: Papers concerning the problem of evil, 1671–1678 (Sleigh, R. C. Jr., Ed. & Trans.). Yale University Press. https://yalebooks.yale.edu/book/9780300089585/confessio-philosophi/ (CP)Google Scholar
Li, W. (Ed.). (2015). Das Recht kann nicht ungerecht sein […]: Beiträge zu Leibniz’ Philosophie der Gerechtigkeit. Studia Leibnitiana, Sonderhefte 44. Steiner. https://www.steiner-verlag.de/Das-Recht-kann-nicht-ungerecht-sein/9783515112130CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Malebranche, N. (1962–1964). Recherche de la vérité, ou l'on traite de la nature de l'esprit de l'homme et de l'usage qu'il en doit faire pour éviter l'erreur dans les sciences. Oeuvres completès de Malebranche, Tome 1–3. Rodis-Lewis, G. (Éd.). Vrin. (Originally published 1674–1675.)Google Scholar
McHugh, C. (2013). Epistemic responsibility and doxastic agency. Philosophical Issues, 23(1), 132157. https://doi.org/10.1111/phis.12007CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Myrdal, P. (2012). Leibniz on agency and force. Uppsala University. https://uu.diva-portal.org/smash/record.jsf?pid=diva2%3A515771&dswid=−8586Google Scholar
Rateau, P. (2019). Leibniz on the problem of evil. Oxford University Press. https://global.oup.com/academic/product/leibniz-on-the-problem-of-evil-9780199996506?cc=ca&lang=en&Google Scholar
Riley, P. (1996). Leibniz’ universal jurisprudence: Justice as the charity of the wise. Harvard University Press. https://www.hup.harvard.edu/catalog.php?isbn=9780674418394CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roinila, M. (2019). Common notions and instincts as sources of moral knowledge in Leibniz's New essays on human understanding. Journal of Early Modern Studies, 8(1), 141169. https://www.pdcnet.org/jems/content/jems_2019_0008_0001_0141_0169CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rutherford, D. (1995). Leibniz and the rational order of nature. Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139172776CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Setiya, K. (2013). Epistemic agency: Some doubts. Philosophical Issues, 23(1), 179198. https://doi.org/10.1111/phis.12009CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shaftesbury, A. A., Earl of. (2001). Characteristicks of men, manners, opinions, times (Vol. 1–3). 6th ed. Liberty Fund. https://oll.libertyfund.org/title/shaftesbury-characteristicks-of-men-manners-opinions-times-3-vols (Originally published 1737–1738.)Google Scholar
Steup, M. (2000). Doxastic voluntarism and epistemic deontology. Acta Analytica, 15(1), 2556. https://citeseerx.ist.psu.edu/document?repid=rep1&type=pdf&doi=e219db1dbd332488bb76dca39e5005758b18f603Google Scholar
Steup, M. (2008). Doxastic freedom. Synthese, 161(3), 375392. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-006-9090-4CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strickland, L. (2009). Leibniz on eternal punishment. British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 17(2), 307331. https://doi.org/10.1080/09608780902761695CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vailati, E. (1990). Leibniz on Locke on weakness of will. Journal of the History of Philosophy, 28(2), 213228. https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.1990.0039CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vargas, E. (2015). Leibniz and Bayle: Two versions of Pyrrhonism. In Leduc, C., Rateau, P., & Solere, J.-L. (Eds.), Leibniz et Bayle: Confrontation et dialogue (pp. 109124). Steiner. https://www.steiner-verlag.de/en/Leibniz-et-Bayle-Confrontation-et-dialogue/9783515106382Google Scholar
Vargas, E. (2016). Defeasible reasoning in the New essays. In Li, W., Beckmann, U., Erdner, S., Errulat, E.-M., Herbst, J., Iwasinski, H., & Noreik, S. (Ed.), Für unser Glück oder das Glück anderer.” Vorträge des X. Internationalen Leibniz-Kongresses, Bd. 5 (pp. 2936). Olms. https://www.nomos-shop.de/olms/titel/fuer-unser-glueck-oder-das-glueck-anderer-id-117094/Google Scholar
Wetherston, B. (2008). Deontology and Descartes's demon. Journal of Philosophy, 150(9), 540569.CrossRefGoogle Scholar