Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-qsmjn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-19T22:47:15.975Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Athletes as Objects of Property: A Kantian Rethinking of Flood v. Kuhn

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  20 July 2015

Get access

Extract

In the 1972 case Flood v. Kuhn, St. Louis Cardinals outfielder Kurt Flood petitioned to the United States Supreme Court arguing that professional baseball’s century-old reserve system was illegal. In the case, which was ultimately unsuccessful but led to the establishment of modern free agency, Flood argued that by granting teams the perpetual right to renew players’ contracts and the right to unilaterally trade players to other teams, the reserve system treated him as “a piece of property to be bought and sold” and reduced him to a “well-paid slave”. In this paper, I justify Flood’s claim by appeal to a Kantian division of rights. I argue for a Kantian conception of rights under which property rights are properly defined as rights in rem in external objects; on the basis that the right a team holds in a ballplayer under the reserve system is alienable and holds against all the world, I argue that it is a right in rem and accordingly constitutes a property right under Kant’s view. I then argue that the reserve system treats the player as a slave by constraining his purposiveness such as to violate a Kantian conception of the innate right of humanity. On this basis I argue that Flood was right to conclude that the reserve system treats the player as an object of property akin to a slave.

Type
Discussion
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 2013

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Sincere thanks to David Lametti, without whom this paper would not have been possible, to Tina Piper and Amar Khoday for helpful discussions, and to the reviewers at the Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence for their comments during revisions.

1. Carfagna, Peter A, “Sports and the Law: Examining the Legal Evolution of America’s Three ‘Major Leagues’Thomson Reuters (United States of America: 2009) at 34 Google Scholar.

2. Note: This use of the term ‘reserved’ here should not be confused with the use of the term when referencing the reserve system.

3. Eckard, W Woodrow, “The Origin of the Reserve Clause: Owner Collusion Versus ‘Public Interest’” (2001) 2 Journal of Sports Economics 113 at 116CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

4. Martindale, Jeff, “Two Strikes: A History and Analysis of Major League Baseball, its Antitrust Exemption, and the Reserve Clause” (1997) 7:3 Journal of Legal Aspects of Sport 174 at 175CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

5. Eckard, supra note 3 at 120.

6. Ibid at 118.

7. Ibid at 117.

8. Sullivan, DA, ed, Early innings: A documentary history of baseball, 1825-1908 (Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1995) at 114-15Google Scholar, cited in ibid at 118.

9. Eckard, ibid at 118.

10. Goldman, Robert M, One Man Out: Curt Flood versus Baseball (Jefferson, NC: McFarand, 2000) at 74.Google Scholar

11. Martindale, supra note 4 at 175.

12. See Philadelphia Ball Club Ltd v Lajoie, 51 A 973 (1902)Google ScholarPubMed [Lajoie]. See also American League Baseball Club of Chicago v Harold H Chase, 86 Misc 441 (1914)Google Scholar.

13. Carfagna, supra note 1 at 35.

14. Federal Baseball Club of Baltimore, Inc v National League of Professional Baseball Clubs, (1922) 259 US 200 at 209Google Scholar.

15. Martindale, supra note 4 at 176.

16. Carfagna, supra note 1 at 36; see also Gardella 172 F2d 402 at 410.

17. Flood v Kuhn, (1972) 407 US 258 Google Scholar.

18. Martindale, supra note 4 at 176.

19. Goldman, supra note 10 at 6.

20. Ibid at 6.

21. Ibid at 73.

22. Ibid at 14.

23. Ibid at 12.

24. Ibid at 12.

25. See Edmonds, Ed, “The Impact of Curt Flood’s Minor League Baseball Experiences on His Lawsuit against Bowie Kuhn” (2008) 16:2 NINE: A Journal of Baseball History and Culture 62 CrossRefGoogle Scholar (“A major part of what ‘sensitized Flood’ was his two years of Minor League baseball in the Jim Crow South” at 63).

26. Goldman, supra note 10 at 33.

27. Ibid at 43; see also 46 Misc 441.

28. Goldman, ibid at 58; see also Gardella, supra note 16 at 409.

29. Eckard, supra note 3 at 113.

30. Goldman, supra note 10 at 6.

31. Kant, Immanuel, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997) at para 4:429Google Scholar.

32. Kant, Immanuel, The Metaphysics of Morals (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996) at para 6:237CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

33. Ibid at 6:237.

34. Hill, Thomas E Jr, “Humanity as an End in Itself” (1980) 91:1 Ethics 84 at 85CrossRefGoogle Scholar. See also ibid at 6:387, 6:391.

35. Kant, supra note 32 at 6:387.

36. Ripstein, Arthur, Force and Freedom: Kant’s Legal and Political Philosophy (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2009) at 15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

37. Ibid at 33.

38. Ibid at 34.

39. Ibid at 44.

40. Ibid at 86.

41. Kant, supra note 32 at 6:260.

42. Ibid at 6:277.

43. Ibid at 6:259.

44. Ibid at 6:260.

45. Ibid at 6:259.

46. Ibid at 6:260, 6:271.

47. Penner, JE, The Idea of Property in Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1997) at 23.Google Scholar

48. Kant, supra note 32 at 6:261.

49. Ibid.

50. Penner, supra note 47 at 23. See also Merrill, Thomas W & Smith, Henry E, “The Property/Contract Interface” (2001) 101 Colum L Rev 773 at 776CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

51. Kant, supra note 32 at 6:274.

52. Penner, supra note 47 at 23.

53. Kant, supra note 32 at 6:270.

54. Penner, supra note 47 at 29.

55. Ibid at 27.

56. Kant, supra note 32 at 6:270.

57. Penner, JE, “The ‘Bundle of Rights’ Picture of Property” (1995-1996) 43 UCLA L Rev 711 at 805Google Scholar [emphasis omitted] [Penner, “Bundle of Rights”].

58. Ripstein, supra note 36 at 88.

59. Kant, supra note 32 at 6:237.

60. Ripstein, supra note 36 at 36.

61. Ibid at 36.

62. Penner, “Bundle of Rights”, supra note 57 at 803.

63. Ripstein, supra note 36 at 115.

64. Penner, supra note 47 at 23.

65. Penner, “Bundle of Rights”, supra note 57 at 803.

66. The obvious counter-example to this point is assignment of a debt. However, a right can only be assigned under the law of obligations if it is patrimonial. The team’s right to a ballplayer is not patrimonial, and is thus not assignable on this ground. Furthermore, Penner gives reason to doubt that the right to claim a debt is properly described as a right in personam, suggesting instead that it is a power in rem. See Penner, supra note 47 (“it is probably better to say that my right is a ‘power in rem‘, a power to change the legal status of the res owned by you” at 30).

67. Penner, “Bundle of Rights”, supra note 57 at 803.

68. Kant, supra note 32 at 6:260, 6:271.

69. Penner, “Bundle of Rights”, supra note 57 at 803.

70. Eckard, supra note 3 at 116.

71. Penner, supra note 47 at 23.

72. Ibid at 23.

73. See Lajoie, supra note 12; Federal Baseball, supra note 14.

74. Kant, supra note 32 at 6:270.

75. Penner, “Bundle of Rights”, supra note 57 at 805.

76. Kant addresses the subject under the heading of the duty of rightful honor. See Kant, supra note 32 (“Rightful honor (honestas iuridica) consists in asserting one’s worth as a human being in relation to others, a duty expressed by the saying, ‘Do not make yourself a mere means for others but be at the same time an end for them.’ This duty will be explained later as the obligation from the right of humanity in our own person (Lex iusti).” at 6:237). See also Ripstein, supra note 36 (Ripstein elaborates that rightful honor entails that “[n]o rightful act on your part can bind you to a condition in which you are subject to another person’s choice,” at 136 and “that a contract cannot turn a person into a thing” at 135).

77. Ripstein, supra note 36 at 136.

78. Ibid at 137.

79. Ibid at 134.

80. Kant, supra note 32 at 6:259.

81. Goldman, supra note 10 at 83.

82. Ripstein, supra note 36 at 41.

83. Ibid at 40.

84. Ibid at 49.

85. Goldman, supra note 10 at 74.

86. Weinrib, Ernest J, “Poverty and Property in Kant’s System of Rights” (2002) 78 Notre Dame L Rev 795 at 804Google Scholar.

87. Goldman, supra note 10 at 83.

88. Ibid at 97.

89. Ibid at xiii.

90. Ibid at 3.

91. Denis, Lara, “Kant’s Ethics and Duties to Oneself” (1997) 78 Pacific Phil Q 321 at 330CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

92. Ibid at 324.

93. Ibid at 330.

94. Ibid at 330.

95. Wood, Allen, “Duties to Oneself, Duties of Respect to Others” in Hill, Thomas E, ed, The Blackwell Guide to Kant’s Ethics (West Sussex: Wiley, 2009) at 243.Google Scholar

96. Ibid at 243.

97. Wood, supra note 95 at 243.

98. Hill, supra note 34 at 85.

99. Goldman, supra note 10 at 98.

100. See e.g., “Mourning, Raptors part ways”, CBC Sports (23 February 2005), online: CBC Sports http://www.cbc.ca/sports/story/2005/02/11/mourning050210.html (“[Alonzo] Mourning never reported to [the Toronto Raptors] after being acquired … Dec. 17 [2004] from the [New Jersey] Nets”).

101. See e.g., Jeff Caplan, “Cuban, Kerr fined by NBA”, ESPN Dallas/Fort Worth (24 May 2010), online: ESPN http://sports.espn.go.com/dallas/nba/news/story?id=5210828 (Dallas Mavericks owner Mark Cuban was fined $100,000 by the National Basketball Association for stating “Come July 1st, yeah, of course, anybody would be interested in [impending Cleveland Cavaliers free agent] LeBron James.”).

102. Goldman, supra note 10 at 80.

103. Ibid at 82.

104. Ibid at 79.

105. Seabury, Susan H, “The Development and Role of Free Agency in Major League Baseball” (1998) 15 Ga U L Rev 335 at 355Google Scholar.

106. Ibid at 84.

107. Ibid at 74.

108. Carfagna, supra note 1 at 79.

109. Goldman, supra note 10 at 93.

110. Ibid at 73.

111. Ibid at 6.

112. Ibid at 6.