Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-ndw9j Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-17T23:19:40.288Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Is there only one innate modular system for spatial navigation?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  27 June 2024

Alexandre Duval*
Affiliation:
School of Philosophy, Australian National University, Canberra, ACT, Australia alexandre.duval@anu.edu.au
*
*Corresponding author.

Abstract

Spelke convincingly argues that we should posit six innate modular systems beyond the periphery (i.e., beyond low-level perception and motor control). I focus on the case of spatial navigation (Ch. 3) to claim that there remain powerful considerations in favor of positing additional innate, nonperipheral modules. This opens the door to stronger forms of nativism and nonperipheral modularism than Spelke's.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press

A central thesis of What Babies Know (Spelke, Reference Spelke2022) is that there are (at least) six innate modular cognitive systems beyond the periphery of the mind, one for each of the following domains: objects, places, numbers, forms, agents, and social beings. Moreover, it seems clear from previous works (e.g., Spelke & Kinzler, Reference Spelke and Kinzler2007) and various discussions in the book that Spelke thinks that there are only a handful of systems that will turn out to be innate and/or nonperipheral modules – either exactly six or only slightly above six – and that research on core knowledge systems will therefore support moderate forms of both nativism and nonperipheral modularism.

My view on the book is that it does an excellent job of arguing for a lower bound on the number of such systems, but that it doesn't give strong reasons why we should stop at six and thus eschew stronger forms of nativism and nonperipheral modularism. It helps to distinguish two questions here: Are there additional innate modules operating within the six domains discussed in the book? Are there additional innate modules operating in other domains? I will make my case by focusing on the first question, and I will do so by taking spatial navigation (Ch. 3) as a case study. (Terminological note: In what follows, I count the properties of domain-specificity and encapsulation as jointly sufficient for modularity.)

Chapter 3 defends an influential idea in navigation research commonly known as the geometric-module hypothesis. On a standard construal, it says that humans and many nonhuman species (including all mammals) possess an innate, domain-specific, encapsulated cognitive system that guides search behavior following sudden disorientation. Moreover, the system is encapsulated by virtue of operating on geometric representations of the three-dimensional surface layout of environments, and nothing else. The chapter doesn't explicitly argue for the view that this is the only innate module involved in spatial navigation. However, it rejects two challenges to that view, which I discuss in turn.

The first challenge relates to the ability to do path integration, which is well-documented in humans and many other species (Etienne & Jeffery, Reference Etienne and Jeffery2004). It is the process by which a subject keeps track of the distance and direction traveled from a certain origin point by relying on self-motion or idiothetic cues (i.e., proprioception, motor efference copy, vestibular signal related to head movements, and optic flow), perhaps along with other cues. Moreover, many researchers (e.g., Gallistel & King, Reference Gallistel and King2010) believe that path integration is underpinned by an innate, domain-specific, encapsulated, nonperipheral cognitive system on something like the following grounds:

  • Innateness: Various species can perform path integration early in their life, with very little experience of the world (Bjerknes, Dagslott, Moser, & Moser, Reference Bjerknes, Dagslott, Moser and Moser2018; Newcombe, Huttenlocher, Drummey, & Wiley, Reference Newcombe, Huttenlocher, Drummey and Wiley1998).

  • Domain-specificity: The system must use linear and angular velocity signals obtained from idiothetic cues to estimate the distance and direction traveled in recent bouts of spatial movements. To do so, it must perform the integration of velocity with respect to time, as well as other very specific mathematical operations suited to the task (Gallistel & King, Reference Gallistel and King2010).

  • Encapsulation: Given the complexity and specificity of the mathematical operations involved, the system can only make use of input representations that have a very specific format. This in turn suggests that it will only rely on the inputs from a handful of systems, those that have evolved to cooperate with it – such as systems for dealing with idiothetic cues, as well as (possibly) systems encoding geometric or featural information about the environment (see below).

  • Nonperipherality: The system deals with abstract properties (location and heading of the subject), and it operates on information pertaining to multiple sense modalities (e.g., vestibular signal and optic flow). In addition, though it guides behavior in a variety of contexts (Etienne & Jeffery, Reference Etienne and Jeffery2004), it is not a low-level motor system either.

Finally, given that this system is triggered under different conditions (oriented navigation) than the geometric module (disoriented navigation), it is often thought that it is distinct from the geometric module.

Spelke's response to this challenge (p. 123) is to deny the last step. She holds that the core place system, a.k.a. the geometric module, is what deals with path integration. On this view, the geometric module is at work in the context of both oriented and disoriented navigation. In support of this claim, she argues that a number of navigation-related neurons in the mammalian hippocampus that underpin path integration display similar signature limits as the geometric module.

This response strikes me as problematic because of various findings about one category of navigation-related neurons: place cells. (Place cells are neurons that become active when an animal represents itself as being in a specific location in an environment.) In particular, I believe that there are good reasons to adopt the two following claims: (1) The implementation of the process of path integration in mammals directly involves place cells; and (2) place cells are sensitive to featural cues (e.g., odors, colors, textures, two-dimensional patterns on three-dimensional surfaces) in contexts where animals are performing path integration. Because it is a central commitment of the geometric-module hypothesis that the geometric module is completely insensitive to featural cues, (1) and (2) together entail that the geometric module can't be the system that implements path integration.

Why we should we believe (1) and (2)? I will start by citing two strands of evidence in favor of (1). First, multiple studies suggest that lesions to the hippocampus proper, where place cells are located, undermines rodents’ ability to go back to their home base when they are in the dark and deprived of olfactory cues (e.g., Maaswinkel, Jarrard, & Whishaw, Reference Maaswinkel, Jarrard and Whishaw1999; Wallace & Whishaw, Reference Wallace and Whishaw2003). Second, Robinson et al. (Reference Robinson, Descamps, Russell, Buchholz, Bicknell, Antonov and Häusser2020) provide strong evidence that we can interfere with subjects’ ability to perform path integration by intervening specifically on place cells. Robinson et al. began by training mice to move on a virtual-reality linear track and to perform licking behavior in a specific zone of the track, near the end, in order to receive a reward. Then, in one of the experimental conditions, when subjects reached a predetermined location around the midway point on the track, they underwent optogenetic activation of place cells that typically fired near the beginning of the track. In this context, mice started overshooting the reward zone and running straight through to the end of linear track significantly more often than before. This strongly suggests that the optogenetic activation of those cells around the midway point often caused the resetting of path integration to a previous position on the track.

Moving on to (2). Because this claim seems widely accepted among neuroscientists working on place cells, I will focus on only one paper: Fischler-Ruiz et al. (Reference Fischler-Ruiz, Clark, Joshi, Devi-Chou, Kitch, Schnitzer and Axel2021) showed that adding odors at specific points on a virtual-reality linear track significantly increases the number of hippocampal cells that qualify as place cells (according to standard methods for identifying such cells based on imaging data) as well as significantly improving the ability of mice to reach a reward zone at the end of the track in the dark. This supports the view that odors, which count as featural cues, can affect place-cell activity in path-integration contexts.

In sum, these findings suggest that proponents of the geometric-module hypothesis must accept that there is an additional innate, nonperipheral module that implements path integration.

The second challenge pertains to a theoretical paper (Duval, Reference Duval2019) that argues, among other things, that extant versions of the geometric-module hypothesis are incomplete because they do not explain how subjects can reliably select the geometric representation of the current environment from memory following a sudden disorientation event.

Drawing on a variety of experiments that involve multiple enclosures, Duval further suggests that geometric-module theorists should posit a domain-specific and encapsulated cognitive mechanism that performs something like environment recognition by virtue of selecting a geometric representation of the current environment in memory. It operates according to the following principle: Select the geometric representation in memory whose content best matches the current environment. If multiple representations match it about equally well, pick the one whose associated featural information best matches the featural cues in the current environment. Assuming that the selection mechanism exists as characterized here, it has to be distinct from the geometric module because it is a central commitment of the geometric-module hypothesis that the latter is insensitive to featural cues. Furthermore, there are number of reasons to think that it would be innate and nonperipheral:

  • Innateness: By hypothesis, the selection mechanism feeds geometric representations to the geometric module that the latter needs to perform its behavior-guiding functions. So, if the latter is innate and operating early in life (as Spelke argues on pp. 134–135), the former would likely be as well.

  • Nonperipherality: The selection mechanism deals with abstract properties (geometry of the three-dimensional surface layout of environments). Moreover, though it guides behavior indirectly through the information it feeds to the geometric module, it is far from a low-level motor system.

Spelke's response to the challenge raised by Duval consists in holding that there would not have been strong evolutionary pressures for a specialized mechanism in charge of environment recognition following a disorientation event. She writes: “Sudden, unknown, passive displacements to entirely new environments […] happened close to never in the lives of animals or people in preindustrial times. […] Although hurricanes or tidal waves may produce this situation, it is unlikely that we or other animals evolved specialized mechanisms for dealing with such rare events” (p. 93). She also points out that animals that actively navigate the world almost always change positions in a continuous fashion: For example, “one step at a time” (p. 93) in the case of animals who stay on the ground. Thus, the process of path integration can help them maintain a sense of where they are in cases when they are not undergoing unexpected, passive displacements (which are very rare).

I want to push back on this analysis. I believe that, contrary to what Spelke claims, there are specific, recurrent situations in the wild where animals would benefit from a specialized mechanism for environment recognition. These are precisely situations where path integration is unreliable. One example comes from exploratory looping behavior. Many species perform looping paths in uncharted territories for purposes of exploration (Eilam, Reference Eilam2014). Animals in this situation would benefit from a system in charge of environment recognition to determine whether they have come back to the environment where they started their exploration and have thus completed their loop. There is no way they can systematically rely on pure idiothetic path integration alone to determine whether have done so, as much work shows that idiothetic path integration quickly accumulates noise (see, e.g., Cheung, Ball, Milford, Wyeth, & Wiles, Reference Cheung, Ball, Milford, Wyeth and Wiles2012; Thrun Reference Thrun, Lakemeyer and Nebel2002). Another case pertains to animals that follow a familiar route in low-visibility conditions – because of fog, smoke, or the lack of sunlight at night – toward a known environment some distance away. For similar reasons about the unreliability of idiothetic path integration, such animals would benefit from a process of environment recognition to determine where they are on their route when there are sudden increases in visibility (e.g., a temporary clear-up in the fog, a better angle of the moon).

Hence, it seems that Spelke's response leaves intact the case, inspired by Duval (Reference Duval2019), for an evolved, innate, modular, and nonperipheral system in charge of environment recognition through geometric-representation selection. More generally, the foregoing discussion supports the view that there (are least) two innate, nonperipheral modules for spatial navigation in human and nonhuman mammals besides the geometric module brilliantly championed by Spelke.

Let me conclude by emphasizing that Spelke has done an enormous service to the cognitive science community with this book by providing a careful, detailed, and extremely important analysis of a very wide range of experimental findings in support of moderate forms of nativism and nonperipheral modularism. Although I don't think that Spelke has given strong reasons to stop at the six innate modular systems that she identifies, the value of What Babies Know cannot be overstated.

Financial support

This work was supported by the Templeton World Charity Foundation (grant TWCF0539).

Competing interest

None.

References

Bjerknes, T. L., Dagslott, N. C., Moser, E. I., & Moser, M.-B. (2018). Path integration in place cells of developing rats. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 115(7), E1637E1646.Google ScholarPubMed
Cheung, A., Ball, D., Milford, M., Wyeth, G., & Wiles, J. (2012). Maintaining a cognitive map in darkness: The need to fuse boundary knowledge with path integration. PLoS Computational Biology, 8(8), e1002651.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Duval, A. (2019). The representation selection problem: Why we should favor the geometric-module framework of spatial reorientation over the view-matching framework. Cognition, 192, 103985.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Eilam, D. (2014). Of mice and men: Building blocks in cognitive mapping. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 47, 393409.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Etienne, A. S., & Jeffery, K. J. (2004). Path integration in mammals. Hippocampus, 14(2), 180192.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fischler-Ruiz, W., Clark, D. G., Joshi, N. R., Devi-Chou, V., Kitch, L., Schnitzer, M., … Axel, R. (2021). Olfactory landmarks and path integration converge to form a cognitive spatial map. Neuron, 109(24), 40364049.e5.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gallistel, C. R., & King, A. P. (2010). Memory and the computational brain: Why cognitive science will transform neuroscience. Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Maaswinkel, H., Jarrard, L. E., & Whishaw, I. Q. (1999). Hippocampectomized rats are impaired in homing by path integration. Hippocampus, 9(5), 553561.3.0.CO;2-G>CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Newcombe, N. S., Huttenlocher, J., Drummey, A. B., & Wiley, J. G. (1998). The development of spatial location coding: Place learning and dead reckoning in the second and third years. Cognitive Development, 13(2), 185200.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robinson, N. T. M., Descamps, L. A. L., Russell, L. E., Buchholz, M. O., Bicknell, B. A., Antonov, G. K., … Häusser, M. (2020). Targeted activation of hippocampal place cells drives memory-guided spatial behavior. Cell, 183(6), 15861599.e10.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Spelke, E. S. (2022). What babies know: Core knowledge and composition (Vol. 1, 1st ed.). Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spelke, E. S., & Kinzler, K. D. (2007). Core knowledge. Developmental Science, 10(1), 8996.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Thrun, S. (2002). Robotic mapping: A survey. In Lakemeyer, G. & Nebel, B. (Eds.), Exploring artificial intelligence in the New Millennium (pp. 135). Morgan Kaufmann.Google Scholar
Wallace, D. G., & Whishaw, I. Q. (2003). NMDA lesions of Ammon's horn and the dentate gyrus disrupt the direct and temporally paced homing displayed by rats exploring a novel environment: Evidence for a role of the hippocampus in dead reckoning. European Journal of Neuroscience, 18(3), 513523.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed