We use cookies to distinguish you from other users and to provide you with a better experience on our websites. Close this message to accept cookies or find out how to manage your cookie settings.
Teleology is about functions, ends, and goals in nature. This Element offers a philosophical examination of these phenomena and aims to reinstate teleology as a core part of the metaphysics of science. It starts with a critical analysis of three theories of function and argues that functions ultimately depend on goals. A metaphysical investigation of goal-directedness is then undertaken. After arguing against reductive approaches to goal-directedness, the Element develops a new theory which grounds many cases of goal-directedness in the metaphysics of powers. According to this theory, teleological properties are genuine, irreducible features of the world.
Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)
References
Adams, F. R. (1979). A goal-state theory of function attributions. Canadian Journal of Philosophy9: 492–518.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alvarado, J. T. and Tugby, M. (2021). A problem for natural-kind essentialism and formal causes. In Jansen, L. and Sandstad, P. (Eds.), Neo-Aristotelian Perspectives on Formal Causation, pp. 201–221. Abingdon: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Amundson, R. and Lauder, G. V. (1994). Function without purpose: The uses of causal role function in evolutionary biology. Biology and Philosophy9: 443–469.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anjum, R. L. and Mumford, S. (2018). What Tends to Be: The Philosophy of Dispositional Modality. Abingdon: Routledge.Google Scholar
Anscombe, G. E. M. (1968). The intentionality of sensation: A grammatical feature. In Butler, R. J. (Ed.), Analytical Philosophy, Second Series, pp. 158–180. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Armstrong, D. M. (1978). Universals and Scientific Realism, Vols. I and II. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Armstrong, D. M. (1997). A World of States of Affairs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Armstrong, D. M. (2004). Truth and Truthmakers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Audi, P. (2012). A clarification and defense of the notion of grounding. In Correia, F. and Schnieder, B. (Eds.), Metaphysical Grounding: Understanding the Structure of Reality, pp. 101–121. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Austin, C. J. (2017). A biologically informed hylomorphism. In Simpson, W. M. R., Koons, R. C., and Teh, N. J. (Eds.), Neo-Aristotelian Perspectives on Contemporary Science, pp. 185–209. Abingdon: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Austin, C. J. and Marmodoro, A. (2017). Structural powers and the homeodynamic unity of organisms. In Simpson, W. M. R., Koons, R. C., and Teh, N. J. (Eds.), Neo-Aristotelian Perspectives on Contemporary Science, pp. 169–184. Abingdon: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Azzouni, J. (2004). Deflating Existential Consequence: A Case for Nominalism. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Babcock, G. (2023). Teleology and function in non-living nature. Synthese201, 112: 1–20.Google Scholar
Barandiaran, X. and Moreno, A. (2008). Adaptivity: From metabolism to behavior. Adaptive Behavior16: 325–344.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bauer, W. A. (2022). Causal Powers and the Intentionality Continuum. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beckner, M. (1959). The Biological Way of Thought. New York: Columbia University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bedau, M. (1992a). Where’s the good in teleology?Philosophy and Phenomenological Research52: 781–806.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bedau, M. (1992b). Goal-directed systems and the good. Monist75: 34–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bellazzi, F. (2022). The emergence of the postgenomic gene. European Journal for the Philosophy of Science12: 1–21.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bellazzi, F. (forthcoming). Biochemical functions. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.Google Scholar
Berman, S. (2020). Platonism and the Objects of Science. London: Bloomsbury.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bigelow, J. and Pargetter, R. (1987). Functions. Journal of Philosophy84: 181–196.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bird, A. (2007). Nature’s Metaphysics: Laws and Properties. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bird, A. (2016). Overpowering: How the powers ontology has overreached itself. Mind125: 341–383.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bird, A. (2018). Fundamental powers, evolved powers, and mental powers. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume92: 247–275.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boorse, C. (1976). Wright on functions. Philosophical Review85: 70–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boorse, C. (1977). Health as a theoretical concept. Philosophy of Science44: 542–573.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boorse, C. (2002). A rebuttal on functions. In Ariew, A., Cummins, R., and Perlman, M. (Eds.), Functions: New Essays in the Philosophy of Psychology and Biology, pp. 63–112. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bouchard, F. (2013). How ecosystem evolution strengthens the case for function pluralism. In Huneman, P. (Ed.), Function: Selection and Mechanisms, pp. 83–95. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bourrat, P. (2021). Function, persistence, and selection: Generalizing the selected-effect account of function adequately. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science90: 61–67.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Braithwaite, R. B. (1953). Scientific Explanation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Brandon, R. N. (2013). A general case for function pluralism. In Huneman, P. (Ed.), Function: Selection and Mechanisms, pp. 97–104. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brentano, F. (2015/1874). Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint. Abingdon: Routledge.Google Scholar
Brown, J. R. (1991). The Laboratory of the Mind: Thought Experiments in the Natural Sciences. Abingdon: Routledge.Google Scholar
Brown, J. R. (1994). Smoke and Mirrors: How Science Reflects Reality. Abingdon: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Canfield, J. (1964). Teleological explanations in biology. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science14: 285–295.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cartwright, N. (1986). Two kinds of teleological explanation. In Donagan, A., Perovich, A. N.Jr., and Wedin, M. I. (Eds.), Human Nature and Natural Knowledge, pp. 201–210. Vol. 89 of Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
Cartwright, N. (1992). Aristotelian natures and the modern scientific method. In Earman, J. (Ed.), Inference, Explanation, and Other Frustrations, pp. 44–71. California: University of California Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cartwright, N. (1999). The Dappled World. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cartwright, N. (2019). Nature, the Artful Modeler: Lectures on Laws, Science, How Nature Arranges the World and How We Can Arrange It Better. Chicago, IL: Open Court.Google Scholar
Cartwright, N. and Pemberton, J. (2013). Aristotelian powers: Without them, what would modern science do? In Greco, J. and Groff, R. (Eds.), Powersand Capacities in Philosophy: The New Aristotelianism, pp. 93–112. New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Christensen, W. D. and Bickhard, M. H. (2002). The process dynamics of normative function.The Monist85: 3–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Corry, R. (2019). Power and Influence: The Metaphysics of Reductive Explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coyne, L. (2016). Phenomenology and teleology: Hans Jonas’s philosophy of life. Environmental Values26: 297–315.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Craver, C. (2013). Functions and mechanisms: A perspectivalist view. In Huneman, P. (Ed.), Function: Selection and Mechanisms, pp. 133–158. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Cummins, R. (1975). Functional analysis. Journal of Philosophy72: 741–765.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Doolittle, W. F. (2013). Is junk DNA bunk? A critique of ENCODE.Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA110: 5294–5300.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ehring, D. (1984a). The system-property theory of goal-directed processes. Philosophy of the Social Sciences14: 497–504.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ehring, D. (1984b). Negative feedback and goals. Nature and System6: 217–220.Google Scholar
Ellis, B. (2001). Scientific Essentialism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Ellis, B. and Lierse, C. (1994). Dispositional essentialism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy72: 27–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Faber, R. J. (1986). Clockwork Garden: On the Mechanistic Reduction of Living Things. Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press.Google Scholar
Feser, E. (2009). Aquinas. Oxford: Oneworld.Google Scholar
Feser, E. (2014). Scholastic Metaphysics. Heusenstamm: Editiones Scholasticae.Google Scholar
Feser, E. (2019). Aristotle’s Revenge: The Metaphysical Foundations of Physical and Biological Science. Neunkirchen: Editiones Scholasticae.Google Scholar
Forber, P. (2020). Contemporary teleology. In McDonough, J. K. (Ed.), Teleology: A History, pp. 255–278. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Franklin, A. and Knox, E. (2018). Emergence without limits: The case of phonons. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics64: 68–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friend, T. and Kimpton-Nye, S. (2023). Dispositions and Powers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gambarotto, A. (2020). Teleology, life and cognition: Reconsidering Jonas’s legacy for a theory of the organism. In Altobrando, A. and Biasetti, P. (Eds.), Natural Born Monads: On the Metaphysics of Organisms and Human Individuals, pp. 243–264. Berlin: De Gruyter.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garson, J. (2016). A Critical Overview of Biological Functions. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garson, J. (2017). A generalized selected effects theory of function. Philosophy of Science84: 523–543.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garson, J. (2018). How to be a function pluralist. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science69: 1101–1122.Google Scholar
Garson, J. (2019a). What Biological Functions Are and Why They Matter. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garson, J. (2019b). There are no ahistorical theories of function. Philosophy of Science86: 1146–1156.Google Scholar
Garson, J. and Piccinini, G. (2014). Functions must be performed at appropriate rates in appropriate situations. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science65: 1–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Germain, P.-L., Ratti, E., and Boem, F. (2014). Junk or functional DNA? ENCODE and the function controversy. Biology and Philosophy29: 807–831.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Giannini, G. (2021). New powers for dispositionalism. Synthese199: 2671–2700.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Giannini, G. and Mumford, S. (2021). Formal causes for powers theorists. In Jansen, L. and Sandstad, P. (Eds.), Neo-Aristotelian Perspectives on Formal Causation, pp. 87–105. Abingdon: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Giannini, G. and Tugby, M. (2020). Potentiality: Actualism minus Naturalism equals Platonism. Philosophical Inquiries8: 117–140.Google Scholar
Giannotti, J. (2021). The identity theory of powers revised. Erkenntnis86: 603–621.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Giroux, E. (2015). Epidemiology and the bio-statistical theory of disease: A challenging perspective. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics36: 175–195.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Godfrey-Smith, P. (1993). Functions: Consensus without unity. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly74: 196–208.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goff, P. (2017). Consciousness and Fundamental Reality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gould, S. J. and Vrba, E. S. (1982). Exaptation – A missing term in the science of form. Paleobiology8: 4–15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffiths, P. E. (1993). Functional analysis and proper function. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science44: 409–422.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffiths, P. E. and Stotz, K. (2013). Genetics and Philosophy: An Introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guo, X.-Y. and Tugby, M. (2023). Collective powers. In Austin, C. J., Marmodoro, A., and Roselli, A. (Eds.), Powers, Parts and Wholes: Essays on the Mereology of Powers, pp. 142–166. Abingdon: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hawthorne, J. and Nolan, D. (2006). What would teleological causation be? In Hawthorne, J. (Ed.), Metaphysical Essays, pp. 265–283. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hegel, G. W. F. (2010/1816). The Science of Logic. G. di Giovanni (trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Heil, J. (2021). Appearance in Reality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hildebrand, T. (2023). Laws of Nature. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hull, D. (1973). Philosophy of Biological Science. Engelwood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Jenkins, C. S. and Nolan, D. (2012). Disposition impossible. Noûs46: 732–753.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jonas, H. (2001). The Phenomenon of Life: Toward a Philosophical Biology. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (2007/1790). Critique of Judgement. J. C. Meredith (trans.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kertész, G. and Kodaj, D. (2023). In defense of teleological intuitions. Philosophical Studies180: 1421–1437.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kimpton-Nye, S. (2020). Necessary laws and the problem of counterlegals. Philosophy of Science87: 518–535.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kimpton-Nye, S. (2021). Reconsidering the dispositional essentialist canon. Philosophical Studies178: 3421–3441.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kimpton-Nye, S. (2022). Pandispositionalism and the metaphysics of powers. Synthese200, 371: 1–21.Google Scholar
Kistler, M. (2006). Causation and Laws of Nature. Abingdon: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, P. (1993). Function and design. Midwest Studies in Philosophy18: 379–397.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koons, R. C. and Pruss, A. (2017). Must functionalists be Aristotelians? In Jacobs, J. D. (Ed.), Causal Powers, 194–204. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, C. M. (2009). Self-Constitution: Agency, Identity, and Integrity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kroll, N. (2017). Teleological dispositions.Oxford Studies in Metaphysics10: 1–37.Google Scholar
Lee, J. G. and McShea, D. W. (2020). Operationalizing goal directedness: An empirical route to advancing a philosophical discussion. Philosophy, Theory and Practice in Biology12, 5: 1–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. (1983). New work for a theory of universals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy61: 343–377.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. (1997). Finkish dispositions. Philosophical Quarterly47: 143–158.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lowe, E. J. (1980). Sortal terms and natural laws: An essay on the ontological status of the laws of nature. American Philosophical Quarterly17: 253–260.Google Scholar
Lowe, E. J. (1982). Laws, dispositions and sortal logic.American Philosophical Quarterly19: 41–50.Google Scholar
Lowe, E. J. (1987). What is the ‘problem of induction’?Philosophy62: 325–340.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lowe, E. J. (2006). The Four-Category Ontology: A Metaphysical Foundation for Natural Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lowe, E. J. (2010). On the individuation of powers. In Marmodoro, A. (Ed.), The Metaphysics of Powers: Their Grounding and Their Manifestations, pp. 8–26. Abingdon: Routledge.Google Scholar
Makin, S. (2006). Aristotle: Metaphysics Book ϴ. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Manier, E. (1971). Functionalism and the negative feedback model in biology. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science8: 225–240.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Manley, D. and Wasserman, R. (2017). Dispositions without teleology. Oxford Studies in Metaphysics10: 47–60.Google Scholar
Marmodoro, A. (2022). What’s dynamic about causal powers? A black box! In Austin, C. J., Marmodoro, A., and Roselli, A. (Eds.), Powers, Time and Free Will, pp. 1–15. Cham: Springer.Google Scholar
Martin, C. B. (1993). Power for realists. In Bacon, J., Campbell, K., and Reinhardt, L. (Eds.), Ontology, Causality, and Mind: Essays in Honour of D. M. Armstrong, pp. 75–86. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Martin, C. B. (1994). Dispositions and conditionals. The Philosophical Quarterly44: 1–8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, C. B. (2008). The Mind in Nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Martin, C. B. and Pfeifer, K. (1986). Intentionality and the non-psychological. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research46: 531–554.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maturana, H. and Varela, F. (1980). Autopoiesis and Cognition: The Realization of the Living. Vol. 42 of Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
Mayr, E. (1988). The multiple meanings of teleological. In Mayr, E. (Ed.), Towards a New Philosophy of Biology, pp. 38–66. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
McDonough, J. K. (Ed.), (2020a). Teleology: A History. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDonough, J. K. (2020b). Not dead yet: Teleology and the ‘scientific revolution’. In McDonough, J. K. (Ed.), Teleology: A History, pp. 150–179. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McKitrick, J. (2003). A case for extrinsic dispositions. Australasian Journal of Philosophy81: 155–174.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McKitrick, J. (2017). Indirect directedness. Oxford Studies in Metaphysics10: 38–46.Google Scholar
McKitrick, J. (2018). Dispositional Pluralism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McLaughlin, P. (2001). What Functions Explain: Functional Explanation and Self-Reproducing Systems. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
McShea, D. W. (2012). Upper-directed systems: A new approach to teleology in biology. Biology and Philosophy27: 663–684.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meincke, A. S. (2019). Autopoiesis, biological autonomy and the process view of life. European Journal for Philosophy of Science9, 5: 1–16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Melander, P. (1997). Analyzing Functions: An Essay on a Fundamental Notion in Biology. Stockholm: Almqvist & Wiksell.Google Scholar
Miller, J. F. A. P. (1971). The immunological role of the thymus. In Samter, M. (Ed.), Immunological Diseases2nd ed, pp. 84–94. Boston, MA: Little, Brown.Google Scholar
Millikan, R. G. (1984). Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories: New Foundations for Realism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Millikan, R. G. (1989). In defense of proper functions. Philosophy of Science56: 288–302.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Millikan, R. G. (1993). White Queen Psychology and Other Essays for Alice. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Mitchell, S. D. (1993). Dispositions or etiologies? A comment on Bigelow and Pargetter. The Journal of Philosophy90: 249–259.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Molnar, G. (2003). Powers: A Study in Metaphysics. Mumford, S. (Ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mossio, M. and Bich, L. (2017). What makes biological organisation teleological?Synthese194: 1089–1114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mossio, M., Saborido, C., and Moreno, A. (2009). An organizational account of biological functions. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science60: 813–841.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mumford, S. (1998). Dispositions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mumford, S. (1999). Intentionality and the physical: A new theory of disposition ascription. The Philosophical Quarterly49: 215–225.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mumford, S. (2006). The ungrounded argument. Synthese149: 471–489.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mumford, S. (2021). Where the real power lies: A reply to Bird. Mind130: 1295–1308.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, E. (1961). The Structure of Science. New York: Harcourt, Brace and World.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, E. (1979). Teleology Revisited and Other Essays in the Philosophy and History of Science. New York: Columbia University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neander, K. (1983). Abnormal psychobiology. PhD dissertation, La Trobe University.Google Scholar
Neander, K. (1991). Functions as selected effects: The conceptual analyst’s defense. Philosophy of Science58: 168–184.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neander, K. (2002). Why history matters: Four theories of functions. In Weingarten, W. and Schlosser, G. (Eds.), Formen der Erklärung in der Biologie, pp. 91–120. Berlin: VWB-Verlag für Wissenschaft Und Bildung.Google Scholar
Neander, K. (2017). Functional analysis and the species design. Synthese194: 1147–1168.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nes, A. (2008). Are only mental phenomena intentional?Analysis68: 205–215.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nissen, L. (1981). Nagel’s self-regulation analysis of teleology. The Philosophical Forum12: 128–138.Google Scholar
Nissen, L. (1997). Teleological Language in the Life Sciences. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Oderberg, D. S. (2008). Teleology: Inorganic and organic. In González, A. M. (Ed.), Contemporary Perspectives on Natural Law, pp. 259–279. Aldershot: Ashgate.Google Scholar
Oderberg, D. S. (2010). The metaphysical foundations of natural law. In Zaborowski, H. (Ed.), Natural Moral Law in Contemporary Society, pp. 44–75. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press.Google Scholar
Oderberg, D. S. (2017). Finality revived: Powers and intentionality. Synthese194: 2387–2425.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oderberg, D. S. (2020). The Metaphysics of Good and Evil. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Oliver, S. (2013). Aquinas and Aristotle’s teleology. Nova et Vetera11: 849–870.Google Scholar
Page, B. (2015). The dispositionalist deity: How God creates laws and why theists should care. Zygon50: 113–137.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Page, B. (2021). Power-ing up neo-Aristotelian natural goodness. Philosophical Studies178: 3755–3775.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Paolini Paoletti, M. (2021a). Functional powers. In Jansen, L. and Sandstad, P. (Eds.), Neo-Aristotelian Perspectives on Formal Causation, pp. 124–148. Abingdon: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Paolini Paoletti, M. (2021b). Teleological powers. Analytic Philosophy62: 336–358.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pittendrigh, C. S. (1958). Adaptation, natural selection and behavior. In Roe, A. and Simpson, G. G. (Eds.), Behavior and Evolution, pp. 390–416. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Place, U. T. (1996). Intentionality as the mark of the dispositional. Dialectica50: 91–120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plantinga, A. (1993). Warrant and Proper Function. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Preston, B. (1998). Why is a wing like a spoon? A pluralist theory of function. Journal of Philosophy95: 215–254.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Prior, E. (1985). What is wrong with etiological accounts of biological function?Pacific Philosophical Quarterly66: 310–328.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raimondi, A. (2021). Crane and the mark of the mental. Analysis81: 683–693.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ransome Johnson, M. (2005). Aristotle on Teleology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rose, D. and Schaffer, J. (2017). Folk mereology is teleological. Noûs51: 238–270.Google Scholar
Rose, D., Schaffer, J., and Tobia, K. (2020). Folk teleology drives persistence judgments. Synthese197: 5491–5509.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenblueth, A. and Wiener, N. (1950). Purposeful and non-purposeful behavior. Philosophy of Science17: 318–326.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenblueth, A., Wiener, N., and Bigelow, J. (1943). Behavior, purpose and teleology. Philosophy of Science10: 18–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ruse, M. (1971). Functional statements in biology. Philosophy of Science38: 87–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Russell, E. S. (1945). The Directiveness of Organic Activities. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sangiacomo, A. (2015). Teleology and agreement in nature. In Campos, A. S. (Ed.), Spinoza: Basic Concepts, pp. 87–102. Exeter: Imprint Academic.Google Scholar
Schaffner, K. F. (1993). Discovery and Explanation in Biology and Medicine. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Scheffler, I. (1959). Thoughts on teleology. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science9: 265–284.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scheffler, I. (1963). The Anatomy of Inquiry. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.Google Scholar
Schelling, F. J. (2000/1800) System des Transzendentalen Idealismus. Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag.Google Scholar
Schmid, S. (2011). Teleology and the dispositional theory of causation in Thomas Aquinas. Logical Analysis and History of Philosophy14: 21–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schrenk, M. (2016). Metaphysics of Science: A Systematic and Historical Introduction. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schwartz, J. (1993). Functional explanation and metaphysical individualism. Philosophy of Science60: 278–301.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smart, B. (2016). Concepts and Causes in the Philosophy of Disease. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sommerhoff, G. (1950). Analytical Biology. London: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sorabji, R. (1964). Function. The Philosophical Quarterly14: 289–302.Google Scholar
Spinoza, B. (2018/1677). Ethics. Kisner, M. J. (Ed.) and M. Silverthorne (trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Stovall, P. (2024). The teleological modal profile and subjunctive background of organic generation and growth. Synthese203, 77: 1–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tahko, T. E. (2020). Where do you get your protein? Or: Biochemical realization. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science71: 799–825.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tan, P. (2017). Interventions and counternomic reasoning. Philosophy of Science84: 956–969.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tan, P. (2019). Counterpossible non-vacuity in scientific practice. The Journal of Philosophy116: 32–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taylor, R. (1950a). Comments on a mechanistic conception of purposefulness. Philosophy of Science17: 310–317.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taylor, R. (1950b). Purposeful and non-purposeful behavior: A rejoinder. Philosophy of Science17: 327–332.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Trestman, M. A. (2012). Implicit and explicit goal-directedness. Erkenntnis77: 207–236.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tugby, M. (2016). On the reality of intrinsically finkable dispositions. Philosophia44: 623–631.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tugby, M. (2020). Organic powers. In Meincke, A. S. (Ed.), Dispositionalism: Perspectives from Metaphysics and Philosophy of Science, pp. 213–238. Cham: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tugby, M. (2021). Grounding theories of powers. Synthese198: 11187–11216.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tugby, M. (2022a). Putting Properties First: A Platonic Metaphysics for Natural Modality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tugby, M. (2022b). The laws of modality. Philosophical Studies179: 2597–2618.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vetter, B. (2015). Potentiality: From Dispositions to Modality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vetter, B. (2018). Evolved powers, artefact powers, and dispositional explanations. Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume92: 277–297.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vetter, B. (2021). Explanatory dispositionalism: What anti-Humeans should say. Synthese199: 2051–2075.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walsh, D. (2008). Teleology. In Ruse, M. (Ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Biology, pp. 113–137. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Walsh, D. M. and Ariew, A. (1996). A taxonomy of functions. Canadian Journal of Philosophy26: 493–514.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, N. E. (2019). The Powers Metaphysic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wimsatt, W. C. (1972). Teleology and the logical structure of function statements. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science3: 1–80.Google Scholar
Witt, C. (2003). Ways of Being: Potentiality and Actuality in Aristotle’s Metaphysics. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Witt, C. (2008). Aristotelian powers. In Groff, R. (Ed.), Revitalizing Causality: Realism about Causality in Philosophy and Social Science, pp. 129–138. Abingdon: Routledge.Google Scholar
Woodfield, A. (1976). Teleology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar