Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-c47g7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-19T15:03:51.969Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

19 - Quantum Mechanics and Molecular Structure: The Case of Optical Isomers

from Part V - The Relationship between the Quantum Ontology and the Classical World

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 April 2019

Olimpia Lombardi
Affiliation:
Universidad de Buenos Aires, Argentina
Sebastian Fortin
Affiliation:
Universidad de Buenos Aires, Argentina
Cristian López
Affiliation:
Universidad de Buenos Aires, Argentina
Federico Holik
Affiliation:
Universidad Nacional de La Plata, Argentina
Get access
Type
Chapter
Information
Quantum Worlds
Perspectives on the Ontology of Quantum Mechanics
, pp. 379 - 392
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2019

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Adler, S. (2003). “Why decoherence has not solved the measurement problem: A response to P. W. Anderson,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 34: 135142.Google Scholar
Bader, R. F. W. (1994). Atoms in Molecules: A Quantum Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bader, R. F. W. (2010a). “The density in density functional theory,” Journal of Molecular Structure: TEOCHEM, 943: 218.Google Scholar
Bader, R. F. W. (2010b). “Definition of molecular structure: By choice or by appeal to observation,” Journal Physical Chemistry A, 114: 74317444.Google Scholar
Bader, R. F. W. (2011). “On the non-existence of parallel universes in chemistry,” Foundations of Chemistry, 13: 1137.Google Scholar
Berlin, Y., Burin, A., and Goldanskii, V. (1996). “The Hund paradox and stabilization of molecular chiral states,” Zeitschrift für Physik D, 37: 333339.Google Scholar
Bub, J. (1997). Interpreting the Quantum World. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Crull, E. (2015). “Less interpretation and more decoherence in quantum gravity and inflationary cosmology,” Foundations of Physics, 45: 10191045.Google Scholar
d’Espagnat, B. (1966). “An elementary note about mixtures,” pp. 185191 in de-Shalit, A., Feshbach, H., and van Hove, L. (eds.), Preludes in Theoretical Physics. Amsterdam: North-Holland.Google Scholar
d’Espagnat, B. (1976). Conceptual Foundations of Quantum Mechanics. Reading, MA: Benjamin.Google Scholar
Dirac, P. A. M. (1929). “Quantum mechanics of many-electron systems,” Proceedings of the Royal Society of London A, 123: 714733.Google Scholar
Fortin, S. and Lombardi, O. (2014). “Partial traces in decoherence and in interpretation: What do reduced states refer to?”, Foundations of Physics, 44: 426446.Google Scholar
Gavroglu, K. and Simões, A. (2012). Neither Physics nor Chemistry: A History of Quantum Chemistry. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Harris, R. and Stodolsky, L. (1981). “Time dependence of optical activity,” The Journal of Chemical Physics, 74: 21452155.Google Scholar
Hendry, R. (2004). “The physicists, the chemists, and the pragmatics of explanation,” Philosophy of Science, 71: 10481059.Google Scholar
Hendry, R. (2008). “Two conceptions of the chemical bond,” Philosophy of Science, 75: 909920.Google Scholar
Hendry, R. (2010). “Ontological reduction and molecular structure,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 41: 183191.Google Scholar
Hendry, R. (2012). “The chemical bond,” pp. 293308 in Woody, A., Hendry, R., and Needham, P. (eds.), Handbook of the Philosophy of Science Volume 6: Philosophy of Chemistry. Amsterdam: Elsevier.Google Scholar
Hendry, R. (2018). The Metaphysics of Chemistry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hettema, H. (2009). “Explanation and theory foundation in quantum chemistry,” Foundations of Chemistry, 11: 145174.Google Scholar
Hettema, H. (2012). Reducing Chemistry to Physics. Limits, Models, Consequences. Groningen, Netherlands: University of Groningen.Google Scholar
Hund, F. (1927). “Zur Deutung der Molekelspektren. III,” Zeitschrift für Physik, 43: 805826.Google Scholar
Labarca, M. and Lombardi, O. (2010). “Why orbitals do not exist?”, Foundations of Chemistry, 12: 149157.Google Scholar
Leach, M. (2013). “Concerning electronegativity as a basic elemental property and why the periodic table is usually represented in its medium form,” Foundations of Chemistry, 15: 1329.Google Scholar
Leggett, A. (1987). “Reflections on the quantum measurement paradox,” pp. 85104 in Hiley, B. and Peat, F. (eds.), Quantum Implications. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Llored, J. -P. (2010). “Mereology and quantum chemistry: The approximation of molecular orbital,” Foundations of Chemistry, 12: 203221.Google Scholar
Lombardi, O. (2014). “Linking chemistry with physics: Arguments and counterarguments,” Foundations of Chemistry, 16: 181192.Google Scholar
Lombardi, O. and Castagnino, M. (2008). “A modal-Hamiltonian interpretation of quantum mechanics,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 39: 380443.Google Scholar
Lombardi, O. and Castagnino, M. (2010). “Matters are not so clear on the physical side,” Foundations of Chemistry, 12: 159166.Google Scholar
Lombardi, O., Castagnino, M., and Ardenghi, J. S. (2010). “The modal-Hamiltonian interpretation and the Galilean covariance of quantum mechanics,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 41: 93103.Google Scholar
Lombardi, O., Fortin, S., and López, L. (2015). “Measurement, interpretation and information,” Entropy, 17: 73107330.Google Scholar
Primas, H. (1983). Chemistry, Quantum Mechanics and Reductionism. Berlin: Springer.Google Scholar
Quack, M. and Stohner, J. (2005). “Parity violation in chiral molecules,” International Journal for Chemistry, 59: 530538.Google Scholar
Scerri, E. (2011). “Editorial 37,” Foundations of Chemistry, 13: 17.Google Scholar
Scerri, E. (2013). “Philosophy of chemistry: Where has it been and where is it going,” pp. 208225 in Llored, J.-P. (ed.), The Philosophy of Chemistry: Practices, Methodologies, and Concepts. Newcastle: Cambridge Scholars Publishing.Google Scholar
Schlosshauer, M. (2007). Decoherence and the Quantum-to-Classical Transition. Berlin: Springer.Google Scholar
Shao, J. and Hänggi, P. (1997). “Control of molecular chirality,” The Journal of Chemical Physics, 107: 99359941.Google Scholar
Sutcliffe, B. and Woolley, G. (2011). “A comment on Editorial 37,” Foundations of Chemistry, 13: 9395.Google Scholar
Sutcliffe, B. and Woolley, G. (2012). “Atoms and molecules in classical chemistry and quantum mechanics,” pp. 387426 in Woody, A., Hendry, R., and Needham, P. (eds.), Handbook of the Philosophy of Science Volume 6: Philosophy of Chemistry. Amsterdam: Elsevier.Google Scholar
Vassallo, A. and Esfeld, M. (2015). “On the importance of interpretation in quantum physics: A reply to Elise Crull,” Foundations of Physics, 45: 15331536.Google Scholar
Vemulapalli, K. (2008). “Theories of the chemical bond and its true nature,” Foundations of Chemistry, 10: 167176.Google Scholar
Wolley, G. (1978). “Must a molecule have a shape?”, Journal of the American Chemical Society, 100: 10731078.Google Scholar
Wolley, G. (1982). “Natural optical activity and the molecular hypothesis,” Structure and Bonding, 52: 135.Google Scholar
Zurek, W. (1981). “Pointer basis of quantum apparatus: Into what mixture does the wave packet collapse?”, Physical Review D, 24: 15161525.Google Scholar
Zurek, W. (1993). “Preferred states, predictability, classicality and the environment-induced decoherence,” Progress of Theoretical Physics, 89: 281312.Google Scholar
Zurek, W. (2003). “Decoherence, einselection, and the quantum origins of the classical,” Reviews of Modern Physics, 75: 715776.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×