Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-5g6vh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-25T08:14:21.908Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

7 - Legal Realism in Context

from Section II - PHILOSOPHY AND METHODS FOR A NEW LEGAL REALISM

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 May 2016

Brian Z. Tamanaha
Affiliation:
Washington University School of Law
Elizabeth Mertz
Affiliation:
American Bar Foundation and University of Wisconsin School of Law
Stewart Macaulay
Affiliation:
University of Wisconsin, Madison
Thomas W. Mitchell
Affiliation:
University of Wisconsin, Madison
Get access

Summary

“We are all realists now,” it is frequently said, yet what legal realism was about remains vigorously debated. When tackling this question, it is common to begin by identifying who counts as legal realists and then identifying what they purportedly believed in. Convention has Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr., John Chipman Gray, Roscoe Pound, and Benjamin Cardozo as antecedents of realism; core realists typically include Karl Llewellyn, Jerome Frank, Felix S. Cohen, Walter Wheeler Cook, Herman Oliphant, Underhill Moore, Hessel Yntema, Charles Clark, Wesley Sturges, William O. Douglas, Leon Green, Max Radin, Thurman W. Arnold, and Joseph C. Hutcheson. Standard accounts of what they stood for are: the legal realists were anti-formalists. They denied that legal rules determined judicial decisions. They saw law as a means to social ends. They advocated a functional view that urges attention to what law actually does. They promoted the application of social science to law. They were rebellious critics of the legal establishment. They denied the claimed neutrality of law. They were New Dealers. What helps keep the dispute alive is that the figures identified as core realists did not all espouse the same positions on these matters.

In this essay I will argue that there is a better way to understand realism, which decenters the core legal realists and what they purportedly believed in. We should see realism instead as a complex of perspectives that characterized a new age of thinking about law. Because the legal realists were not unique in holding these views, I argue, it is a mistake to think that the key to understanding realism can be found through a close examination of their particular positions, especially since they disagreed amongst themselves a great deal. To establish this I will alternate between two contexts: the narrow context of the Llewellyn-Pound exchange, which first brought attention to “legal realism,” and the broad context of widely expressed realistic views in the generation preceding this exchange.

The diversity of views among the named legal realists is often suppressed by jurists who tell us what legal realism was about, but Karl Llewellyn emphasized this at the beginning, the middle, and the final words of his essay clarifying realism.

Type
Chapter
Information
The New Legal Realism
Translating Law-and-Society for Today's Legal Practice
, pp. 147 - 168
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2016

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Beale, Joseph H. 1914. “The Necessity for a Study of Legal System.” AALS Proceedings31–45.
Bigelow, Melville. 1905. “A Scientific School of Legal Thought.” Green Bag 17(1): 1–16.Google Scholar
Boudin, L.B. 1911. “Government by Judiciary.” Political Science Quarterly 26: 238–270.Google Scholar
Brandeis, Louis D. 1916. “The Living Law.” Illinois Law Review 10: 461–471.Google Scholar
Cardozo, Benjamin N. 1928. The Paradoxes of Law. New York: Columbia University Press.
Clark, Walter. 1950. “Government by Judges.” In The Papers of Walter Clark, Vol. Two, 1857–1924, edited by Brooks, Aubrey Lee and Lefler, Hugh Talmage, 572–594. Chapel Hill: North Carolina Press.
Coles, Walter D. 1893. “Politics and the Supreme Court of the United States.” American Law Review 27: 182–208.Google Scholar
Colt, LeBaron. 1903. “Law and Reasonableness.” American Law Review 17: 657–676.Google Scholar
Cook, Walter Wheeler. 1927. “Scientific Method and the Law.” American Bar Association Journal 13: 303–309.Google Scholar
Dagan, Hanoch. 2007. “The Realist Conception of Law.” Toronto Law Journal 57: 607–660.Google Scholar
Dodd, W.F. 1909. “The Growth of Judicial Power.” Political Science Quarterly 24: 193–207.Google Scholar
Dodd, W.F. 1911. “The Recall and the Political Responsibility of Judges.” Michigan Law Review 10: 79–92.Google Scholar
Ehrlich, Eugen 1917. Judicial Freedom of Decision: Its Principles and Objects, in Science of Legal Method: Selected Essays by Various Authors. Translated by Bruncken, Ernest. Boston: Boston Book Company.
Ehrlich, Eugen. 1937. Fundamental Principles of the Sociology of Law. Translated by Moll, Walter. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Ewing, Thomas. 1890. “Codification.” Albany Law Journal 41: 439–442.Google Scholar
Frankfurter, Felix, Llewellyn, Karl N., and Sunderland, Edson R.. 1929. “The Conditions for and the Aims and Methods of Legal Research.” American Law School Review 6: 663–681.Google Scholar
Gordon, Robert W. 2004. “Professors and Policymakers: Yale Law School Faculty in the New Deal and After.” In History of the Yale Law School: The Tricentennial Lectures, edited by Kronman, Anthony T., 75–137. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Hammond, William G. 1881. “American Law Schools, Past and Future.” Southern Law Review 7: 400–429.Google Scholar
Hertogh, Marc, ed. 2009. Living Law: Reconsidering Eugen Ehrlich. Oxford: Hart Publishing.
Holmes, Oliver Wendell. 1897. “The Path of the Law.” Boston Law School Magazine 1(4): 1–18.Google Scholar
Holmes, Oliver Wendell. 1899. “Law in Science and Science in Law.” Harvard Law Review 12: 443–463.Google Scholar
Hull, N.E.H. 1997. Roscoe Pound and Karl Llewellyn: Searching for an American Jurisprudence. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Kreitner, Roy. 2010. “Biographing Realist Jurisprudence.” Law & Social Inquiry 35: 765–791.Google Scholar
Larremore, Wilbur. 1904. “Judicial Legislation in New York.” Yale Law Journal 14: 312–321.Google Scholar
Lewis, William Draper. 1913. “Social Sciences as the Basis of Legal Education.” University of Pennsylvania Law Review 61(8): 531–539.Google Scholar
Llewellyn, Karl. 1930. “A Realistic Jurisprudence – The Next Step.” Columbia Law Review 30: 431–465.Google Scholar
Llewellyn, Karl. 1931. “Some Realism About Realism – Responding to Dean Pound.” Harvard Law Review 44: 1222–1264.Google Scholar
Llewellyn, Karl. 1940. “The Normative, The Legal, and the Law-Jobs: The Problem of Juristic Method.” Yale Law Journal 49: 1355–1400.Google Scholar
Llewellyn, Karl. 1951. The Bramble Bush: On Our Law and Its Study. New York: Oceana Publishing.
Llewellyn, Karl. 1960. The Common Law Tradition: Deciding Appeals. Boston: Little, Brown.
Lurton, Horace H. 1911. “A Government of Law or a Government of Men?North American Review 193: 9–25.Google Scholar
Monroe, Alan H. 1924. “The Supreme Court and the Constitution.” American Political Science Review 18: 737–759.Google Scholar
Myers, Gustavus. 1912. History of the Supreme Court of the United States. New York: Burt Franklin.
Owen, Robert L. 1911. “The Right of Election and Recall of Federal Judges.” Maine Law Review 9: 82–107.Google Scholar
Pennoyer, Sylvester. 1896. “The Case of Marbury v. Madison.” American Law Review 30: 188–202.Google Scholar
Pound, Roscoe. 1907a. “Common Law and Legislation.” Harvard Law Review 21: 383–487.Google Scholar
Pound, Roscoe. 1907b. “The Need of a Sociological Jurisprudence.” Green Bag 19: 607–615.Google Scholar
Pound, Roscoe. 1908. “Mechanical Jurisprudence.” Columbia Law Review 8: 605–623.Google Scholar
Pound, Roscoe. 1910. “Law in Books and Law in Action.” American Law Review 44: 12–36.Google Scholar
Pound, Roscoe. 1931. “The Call for a Realist Jurisprudence.” Harvard Law Review 44: 697–711.Google Scholar
Rabban, David M. 2012. Law's History: American Legal Thought and the Transatlantic Turn to History. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Roe, Gilbert E. 1912. Our Judicial Oligarchy. New York: Huebosch.
Rose, Uriah M. 1902. “American Bar Association.” Albany Law Journal 64: 333–338.Google Scholar
Savage, Albert R. 1913. “Some Sore Spots.” Maine Law Review 7: 29–43.Google Scholar
Schauer, Frederick. 2012. “Legal Realism Untamed.” Texas Law Review 91: 749–780.Google Scholar
Schlegel, John Henry. 1995. American Legal Realism and Empirical Social Science. Durham: University of North Carolina Press.
Schroeder, Theodore. 1912. “Social Justice and the Courts.” Yale Law Journal 22: 19–29.Google Scholar
Schroeder, Theodore. 1918. “The Psychologic Study of Judicial Decisions.” California Law Review 6: 89–113.Google Scholar
Suchman, Mark, and Mertz, Elizabeth. 2010. “Toward a New Legal Empiricism: Empirical Legal Studies and New Legal Realism.” Annual Review of Law and Social Science 6(1): 555–576.Google Scholar
Tamanaha, Brian Z. 2010. Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Tamanaha, Brian Z. 2011. “A Vision of Socio-Legal Change: Rescuing Ehrlich from Living Law.” Law & Social Inquiry 36: 297–318.Google Scholar
Tamanaha, Brian Z. 2012. Failing Law Schools. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Tamanaha, Brian Z. 2015. “The Third Pillar of Jurisprudence: Social Legal Theory.” William and Mary Law Review 56(6): 2235–2277.Google Scholar
Thompson, Seymour D. 1896. “Government by Lawyers.” American Law Review 30: 672–701.Google Scholar
Tiedeman, Christopher G. 1892. “Dictum and Decision.” Columbia Law Times 6: 35–39.Google Scholar
Tiedeman, Christopher G. 1896. “The Doctrine of Stare Decisis.” University Law Review 3: 11–26.Google Scholar
Twining, William. 1985. “Talk About Realism.” New York University Law Review 60: 329–384.Google Scholar
Twining, William. (1973/1985) 2012. Karl Llewellyn and The Realist Movement, edition (with Afterword). New York: Cambridge University Press.
Whitney, Edward B. 1904. “The Doctrine of Stare Decisis.” Michigan Law Review 3: 89–107.Google Scholar
Willcox, Walter F. 1913. “The Need of Social Statistics as an Aid to the Courts.” American Journal of Sociology 18: 601–612.Google Scholar
Yale Editorial Board. “Comments.” Yale Law Journal 27: 102–127.
Young, John E. 1917. “The Law as an Expression of Community Ideals and the Lawmaking Functions of Courts.” Yale Law Journal 27: 1–33.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×