Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-qsmjn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-25T00:41:40.729Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

19 - Metaphor and irony: Two levels of understanding

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2012

Ellen Winner
Affiliation:
Boston College
Howard Gardner
Affiliation:
Harvard Graduate School of Education
Andrew Ortony
Affiliation:
Northwestern University, Illinois
Get access

Summary

In defense of the literal–nonliteral distinction

Speakers often do not say what they mean. Both literal and nonliteral utterances require the listener to go beyond what is said to infer what is meant. Even the most literal of utterances is meant to convey unstated implications. To state (truthfully) that it is raining can mean not only that it is raining but also (depending on the context) (a) “Take your umbrella,” (b) “The picnic is off,” (c) “I told you so,” and so forth. Despite the fact that these meanings are unstated, they are usually effortlessly apprehended, and conversataion typically proceeds thereafter in seamless fashion. A multitude of cues enables the listener to infer what is meant.

Since in both literal and nonliteral discourse speakers invariably mean more than they say, the distinction between literal and nonliteral usage cannot rest on whether the speaker says what is meant. Instead, the distinction rests on the reverse – whether the speaker means what is said (Searle, this volume). In literal discourse, speakers mean what they say and more. In nonliteral discourse, speakers do not mean what they say. Hence, what is said must be used but discounted in the interpretation process.

In addition, the distinction between literal and nonliteral discourse in our view rests on the relation between what is said and what is meant. In literal utterances this relation is one of consonance: the implied meanings are consistent with the sentence meaning though they may range far afield from the actual statement, as in (b) and (c) above.

Type
Chapter
Information
Metaphor and Thought , pp. 425 - 444
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1993

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×