Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Home
  • Get access
    Check if you have access via personal or institutional login
  • Cited by 1
  • Online publication date: March 2017

Coercion vs. indeterminacy in opaque verbs

Summary

Introduction. This paper is about the semantic analysis of opaque verbs such as seek and owe, which allow for unspecific readings of their indefinite objects. One may be looking for a good car without there being any car that one is looking for; or, one may be looking for a good car in that a specific car exists that one is looking for. It thus appears that there are two interpretations of these verbs—a specific and an unspecific one—and one may wonder how they are related. The present paper is a contribution to this question.

History

Paris. The time of the holy inquisition. Opaque verbs differ in their semantic behaviour from ordinary verbs. This phenomenon was already known to the medieval logician Buridanus:

I posit the case that for a good service you performed forme, I promised you a good horse. [] And since I owe you this, until I have paid that concerning the payment of which I have obligated myself [], you could rightly take action against me to bring about payment to you of a horse, which you could not do if I did not owe you. [] But the opposite is argued in a difficult way.

[Buridanus (1966 [1350]: 137)]

The followingmodern version of the opposite argument is less verbose than the original:

Let us then have our horse-coper arguing again. “If I owe you a horse, then I owe you something. And if I owe you something, then there is something I owe you. And this can only be a thoroughbred of mine: you aren't going to say that in virtue of what I said there's something else I owe you. Very well, then: by your claim, there's one of my thoroughbreds I owe you. Please tell me which one it is.”

[Geach (1965: 430)]

The two arguments are based on two different ways of reading the sentence under debate (1) — an obvious, unspecific interpretation and a somewhat remote, specific one.

[1] M., Aloni, Quantification under conceptual covers, Dissertation, University of Amsterdam, 2001.
[2] N., Asher, A typology for attitude verbs and their anaphoric properties, Linguistics and Philosophy, vol. 10 (1987), pp. 125–198.
[3] M., Bennett, A variation and extension of a montague fragment of English, Montague grammar (B., Partee, editor), Academic Press, New York, 1976, pp. 119–163.
[4] R., Blutner, Lexical semantics and pragmatics, Semantics (F., Hamm and T. E., Zimmermann, editors), Buske, Hamburg, 2002, pp. 27–58.
[5] J., Buridanus, Sophisms on meaning and truth, Translated by T. K., Scott, Appliton-Century- Crofts, New York, 1966, (= Sophismata, 1350).
[6] A., Copestake and T., Briscoe, Semi-productive polysemy and sense extension, Journal of Semantics, vol. 12 (1995), pp. 15–67.
[7] M. J., Cresswell, Logics and languages, Methuen, London, 1973.
[8] M. J., Cresswell and A., von Stechow, De re belief generalized, Linguistics and Philosophy, vol. 5 (1982), pp. 503–535.
[9] H., de Swart, Tense, aspect and coercion in a cross-linguistic perspectives, Proceedings of the Berkeley formal grammar conference workshops (M. Butt and T. H. King, editors), On-line publication 2000. cslipublications.stanford.edu/LFG/5/bfg00/bfg00-toc.html.
[10] G., Forbes, Objectual attitudes, Linguistics and Philosophy, vol. 23 (2000), pp. 141–183.
[11] G., Frege, Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik, Koebner, Breslau, 1884, [The Foundations of Arithmetic. Translated by J. L., Austin. Oxford 1950].
[12] P., Geach, A medieval discussion of intentionality, Logic, methodology and philosophy of science (Y., Bar-Hillel, editor), North Holland, Amsterdam, 1965, pp. 425–433.
[13] I., Heim, The semantics of definite and indefinite noun phrases, Dissertation, UMass at Amherst, 1982.
[14] I., Heim, Presupposition projection and the semantics of attitude verbs, Journal of Semantics, vol. 9 (1992), pp. 183–221.
[15] I., Heim and A., Kratzer, Semantics in generative grammar, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1998.
[16] H., Hendriks, Studied flexibility, Dissertation, University of Amsterdam, 1993.
[17] T. M. V., Janssen, Compositionality, Handbook of logic and language (J., van Benthem and A., ter Meulen, editors), (With an appendix by B. H., Partee), Elsevier, Amsterdam, 1997, pp. 417–473.
[18] H., Kamp, A theory of truth and semantic representation, Formal methods in the study of language, Part 1 (J. A. G., Groenendijk et al., editors),Mathematical Centre Tracts, Amsterdam, 1981, pp. 277–322.
[19] D., Kaplan, Quantifying in, Words and objections: Essays on the work of W. V. Quine (D., Davidson and J., Hintikka, editors), Reidel, Dordrecht, 1969, pp. 206–242.
[20] D., Kaplan, How to Russell a Frege-Church, Journal of Philosophy, vol. 72 (1975), pp. 716– 729.
[21] D., Kaplan, Demonstratives. an essay on the semantics, logic, metaphysics and epistemology of demonstratives and other indexicals, Themes from Kaplan (J., Almog, J., Perry, and H., Wettstein, editors), Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1989, pp. 481–563.
[22] M., Krifka, For a structured meaning account of questions and answers, Audiatur Vox Sapientiae (C., Fèry andW. Sternefeld, editors), Akademic-Verlag, Berlin, 2001, pp. 287–319.
[23] R., Larson, M., den Dikken, and P., Ludlow, Intensional transitive verbs and abstract clausal complementation, Manuscript, SUNY at Stony Brook, 1999.
[24] D., Lewis, Attitudes de dicto and de se, The Philosophical Review, vol. 88 (1979), pp. 513– 543.
[25] D., Lewis, What puzzling Pierre does not believe, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, vol. 59 (1981), pp. 283–289.
[26] F., Moltmann, Intensional verbs and quantifiers, Natural Language Semantics, (1997), pp. 1–52.
[27] R., Montague, On the nature of certain philosophical entities, Monist, vol. 53 (1969), pp. 159–195.
[28] R., Montague, English as a formal language, Linguaggi nella societ`a e nella tecnica (B., Visentini, editor), Edizioni di Communit`a,Milan, 1970a, pp. 189–223.
[29] R., Montague, Universal grammar, Theoria, vol. 36 (1970b), pp. 373–398.
[30] R., Montague, The proper treatment of quantification in ordinary English, Approaches to natural language (J., Hintikka et al., editors), Reidel, Dordrecht, 1973, pp. 221–242.
[31] B., Partee, Noun phrase interpretation and type shifting principles, Studies in discourse representation theory and the theory of generalized quantifiers (J., Groenendijk et al., editors), Foris, Dordrecht, 1987, pp. 115–143.
[32] B., Partee, Montague grammar, Handbook of logic and language (J., van Benthem and A., ter Meulen, editors), [With H. Hendriks], Elsevier, Amsterdam, 1997, pp. 5–91.
[33] B., Partee and M., Rooth, Generalized conjunction and type ambiguity, Meaning, use, and interpretation of language (R., Bäuerle et al., editors), de Grugter, Berlin, 1983, pp. 361–383.
[34] J., Pustejovsky, Type coercion and lexical selection, Semantics and the lexicon (J., Pustejovsky, editor), Kluwer, Dordrecht, 1993, pp. 73–94.
[35] W. V. O., Quine, Quantifiers and propositional attitudes, Journal of Philosophy, vol. 53 (1956), pp. 177–187.
[36] W. V. O., Quine, Word and object, MIT Press, Cambridge,Mass., 1960.
[37] M., Rooth and B., Partee, Conjunction, type ambiguity, and wide scope “or”, Proceedings of the 1st west coast conference on formal linguistics (Stanford) (D. Flickinger et al., editors), 1982, pp. 353–362.
[38] T. E., Zimmermann, On the proper treatment of opacity in certain verbs, Natural Language Semantics, vol. 1 (1993), pp. 149–179.
[39] T. E., Zimmermann, Free choice disjunction and epistemic possibility, Natural Language Semantics, vol. 8 (2000), pp. 255–290.
[40] T. E., Zimmermann, Unspecificity and intensionality, Audiatur Vox Sapientiae (C., Fèry and W., Sternefeld, editors), Akademic-Verlag, Berlin, 2001, pp. 514–533.