Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-45l2p Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-25T15:18:07.794Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Introduction

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 December 2011

Mark Norris Lance
Affiliation:
Georgetown University, Washington DC
John O'Leary-Hawthorne
Affiliation:
Syracuse University, New York
Get access

Summary

PHILOSOPHICAL ACCOUNTS OF MEANING

Daniel Dennett once invited us to consider super-Martians who were highly advanced scientifically yet lacked all intentional concepts. They spoke the language of austere physics and were capable of perceiving and describing the world at the micro-level. If such beings could accurately report happenings in their environment, make predictions, and generally live out their lives wholly within the scientific image, what would they be missing, Dennett wondered, by virtue of lacking intentional concepts? Dennett's answer was that they would miss out on various higher-level patterns, describable by way of mentalistic and semantic vocabulary. Such patterns are available to us by virtue of our understanding of such vocabulary, and we rely inescapably on it.

Such an answer, in outline, is fairly standard today. That is, it is fair to say that the general consensus in modern philosophy is that semantic talk – to focus on the species of concern to us – is descriptive of some sort of high-level pattern. There is, to be sure, a fair range of disagreement as to what sort of pattern it is. For some (Field, Devitt) it is a pattern of causal relations between humans, their language, and macroscopic objects; for others (Putnam at one point, Lycan) it is purely the functional organization of individual thought, while various philosophers extend this individualism to include either relations to external objects (Putnam at another point), or relations among the people in one's society (Burge, perhaps Sellars, and Putnam at yet a third point).

Type
Chapter
Information
The Grammar of Meaning
Normativity and Semantic Discourse
, pp. 1 - 16
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1997

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×