Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-sxzjt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-25T03:54:06.480Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

13 - The contribution (and drawbacks) of models to the study of concepts

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2012

Emmanuel M. Pothos
Affiliation:
Swansea University
Andy J. Wills
Affiliation:
University of Exeter
Get access

Summary

A book that focuses on computational models carries with it the presupposition that modelling is an important and useful activity. And so it is. But why? What does modelling add that other kinds of theorizing or empirical work do not? And what can go wrong in modelling? In this chapter, I will take a step back to address these questions. I cannot hope to teach much to experienced researchers in this field, but I think that for students, newcomers, and sceptics, it is useful to consider what modelling adds and how it can sometimes detract from the enterprise of doing cognitive psychology. On the whole, I think that the contribution of computational models has been positive to our understanding of concepts. But at the same time, I think that some of the persisting shortcomings in the field of concepts are in part due to an emphasis on modelling or to the way researchers use models as a tool to enhance our understanding of concepts.

We can learn about concepts by doing category-learning experiments, by making cross-cultural comparisons, by carrying out observational studies, and by studying the properties of natural categories, among other techniques. Each of these will tell us some things but cannot tell us other things. So it is with building models of concepts. A chapter such as this one might focus more on problems than on benefits, but it should be understood that there are pitfalls and limitations in every method.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Anderson, J. R. (1976). Language, Memory, and Thought. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.Google Scholar
Economist, The (July 18, 2009). The other-worldly philosophers. The Economist, 392 (8640), 65–67.
Heit, E., & Rubinstein, J. (1994). Similarity and property effects in inductive reasoning. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 20, 411–422.Google ScholarPubMed
Murphy, G. L. (2005). The study of concepts inside and outside the lab: Medin vs. Medin. In Ahn, W., Goldstone, R. L., Love, B. C., Markman, A. B., & Wolff, P. (eds.), Categorization Inside and Outside the Lab: Essays in Honor of Douglas Medin (pp. 179–195). Washington, DC: APA.Google Scholar
Osherson, D. N., Smith, E. E., Wilkie, O., López, A., & Shafir, E. (1990). Category-based induction. Psychological Review, 97, 185–200.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Posner, M. I., & Keele, S. W. (1970). Retention of abstract ideas. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 83, 304–308.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Proffitt, J. B., Coley, J. D., & Medin, D. L. (2000). Expertise and category-based induction. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 26, 811–828.Google ScholarPubMed
Rehder, B. (2009). Causal-based property generalization. Cognitive Science, 33, 301–344.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ross, B. H. (1996). Category representations and the effects of interacting with instances. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 22, 1249–1265.Google Scholar
Ross, B. H., & Murphy, G. L. (1999). Food for thought: cross-classification and category organization in a complex real-world domain. Cognitive Psychology, 38, 495–553.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schank, R. C., & Abelson, R. P. (1977). Scripts, Plans, Goals and Understanding. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.Google Scholar
Sloman, S. A. (1993). Feature-based induction. Cognitive Psychology, 25, 231–280.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×