Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Home
  • Print publication year: 2008
  • Online publication date: June 2012

I - Settling Moral Controversy

Summary

Settlement

The need for legal reasoning comes about when members of a community confer authority on certain individuals to settle moral controversies. The controversies that concern us arise in a community whose members agree on moral values at a fairly high level of generality and accept these values as guides for their own action. Individuals who are fundamentally like-minded and well intentioned may nevertheless differ about the specific implications of moral values, or they may be uncertain about the best ways to realize shared values. Recognizing that controversies of this kind are inevitable, the community can reduce the moral costs of disagreement and uncertainty by delegating a power of settlement to a chosen authority.

Settlement, as we use the term, is not simply choice of a solution. It entails reasoning, by which we mean conscious, language-based deliberation about reasons for the choice ultimately made. The members of our imagined community have not agreed to flip a coin; they have selected a human authority to translate the values that serve as reasons for action within the community into solutions to practical problems. Given the flaws of human reasoning, the solutions the authority endorses may not be justified in the sense that they are morally correct. But, because the authority's task is to settle what the community's values require in practice, its conclusions must be susceptible to justificatory argument. They cannot refer to intuition alone.

Alexander, Larry and Sherwin, Emily, The Rule of Rules: Morality, Rules, and the Dilemmas of Law 11–15 (Durham: Duke University Press 2001)
Raz, Joseph, Ethics in the Public Domain 187–92 (Oxford: Clarendon Press 1994)
Eisenberg, Melvin Aron, The Nature of the Common Law 4–7 (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press 1988)
Kavka, Gregory S., Why Even Morally Perfect People Would Need Government, 12 Soc. Phil. & Pol'y 1 (1995).
Sloman, Steven A., Two Systems of Reasoning, in Heuristics and Biases: The Psychology of Intuitive Judgment 379–96 (Gilovich, Thomas, Griffin, Dale, and Kahneman, Daniel, eds., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 2002)
Haidt, Jonathan, The Emotional Dog and Its Rational Tail: A Social Intuitionist Approach to Moral Judgment, 4 Psychological Review 814, 818 (2001)
Blackburn, Simon, Think 193–232 (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1999)
Schauer, Frederick, Playing by the Rules: A Philosophical Examination of Rule-Based Decision-Making in Life and Law 53–54 (Oxford: Clarendon Press 1991)
Raz, Joseph, The Morality of Freedom 57–62 (Oxford: Clarendon Press 1986)
Raz, Joseph, The Authority of Law 16–19, 22–23, 30–33 (Oxford: Clarendon Press 1979).
Alexander, and Sherwin, , The Deceptive Nature of Rules, 142 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1191, 1192–93 (1994)
Schauer, Frederick, Prescriptions in Three Dimensions, 82 Iowa L. Rev. 911, 916–18 (1997)
Hurd, Heidi M., Moral Combat 214–21 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1999)
Campbell, Tom D., The Legal Theory of Ethical Positivism 6, 50, 53, 58 (Aldershot: Dartmouth Publishing 1996)
Coleman, Jules L., Authority and Reason, in The Autonomy of Law: Essays on Legal Positivism 304–5 (George, Robert P., ed., Oxford: Clarendon Press 1996)
Regan, Donald H., Authority and Value: Reflections on Raz's Morality of Freedom, 62 S. Calif. L. R. 995, 1006–10 (1989)
Postema, Gerald J., Coordination and Convention at the Foundation of Law, 11 J. Legal Stud. 165, 172–86 (1982).
Hart, H. L. A., The Concept of Law 78–79, 89–96 (Oxford: Clarendon Press 1961).
Sunstein, Cass R., Legal Reasoning and Political Conflict 27–28 (New York: Oxford University Press 1996)
Kaplow, Louis, Rules versus Standards: An Economic Analysis, 42 Duke L.J. 557, 560–62 (1992)
Powers, William, Structural Aspects of the Impact of Law on Moral Duty within Utilitarianism and Social Contract Theory, 26 U.C.L.A. L. Rev. 1263, 1270–93 (1979)
Ehrlich, Isaac and Posner, Richard A, An Economic Analysis of Legal Rulemaking, 3 J. Legal Stud. 257, 261–71 (1974)
Fumerton, Richard A., Reason and Morality: A Defense of the Perspective 208–23, 234–39 (Ithaca: Cornell University Press 1990)
Hurd, Heidi M., Challenging Authority, 100 Yale L.J. 1011 (1991)
Kavka, Gregory, The Toxin Puzzle, 43 Analysis 33 (1983)
Kavka, Gregory, Some Paradoxes of Deterrence, 75 J. Phil. 285 (1978)
Shapiro, Scott J., The Difference That Rules Make, in Analyzing Law 33, 45–54 (Bix, Brian, ed., Oxford: Clarendon Press 1998)
Gauthier, David, Commitment and Choice: An Essay on the Rationality of Plans, in Ethics, Rationality, and Economic Behavior 217 (Farina, Francesco, Hahn, Frank, and Vanncucci, Stefano, eds., Oxford: Clarendon Press 1996)
McClennon, Edward F., Pragmatic Rationality and Rules, 26 Phil. and Pub. Aff. 210 (1997)
Murphy, Mark C., Surrender of Judgment and the Consent Theory of Political Authority, 16 Law and Phil. 115 (1997).
Alexander, Larry, The Gap, 14 Harv. J. L. & Pub. Pol. 695 (1991)
Schauer, Frederick, Rules and the Rule of Law, 14 Harv. J. L. & Pub. Pol. 645, 676 n. 66 (1991)
Postema, Gerald J., Positivism, I Presume? … Comments on Schauer's Rules and the Rule of Law, 14 Harv. J. L. & Pub. Pol. 797, 815–16 (1991).
Hurd, Heidi M., Justifiably Punishing the Justified, 90 Mich. L. Rev. 2203, 2279–334 (1992).
Greenawalt, Kent, Law and Objectivity 34–89 (New York: Oxford University Press 1992)
Coleman, Jules L. and Leiter, Brian, Determinacy, Objectivity, and Authority, 142 U. Pa. L. Rev.549 (1992)
Solum, Lawrence B., On the Indeterminacy Crisis: Critiquing Critical Dogma, 54 U. Chi. L. Rev. 462 (1987).
Altman, Andrew, Legal Realism, Critical Legal Studies and Dworkin, 15 Phil. & Pub. Aff. 205 (1986)
D'Amato, Anthony, Pragmatic Indeterminacy, 85 Northwestern U. L. Rev. 171–74 (1990)
Kairys, David, Law and Politics, 52 G.W. L. Rev. 243 (1984)
Singer, Joseph, The Player and the Cards: Nihilism and Legal Theory, 94 Yale L.J. 1 (1984)
Weinreb, Lloyd L., Legal Reason: The Use of Analogy in Legal Argument 88–91, 103–5 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 2005)
Burton, Steven J., An Introduction to Law and Legal Reasoning 18–20, 44, 52–57 (Boston: Little, Brown 1995)
Llewellyn, Karl, The Bramble Bush: On Our Law and Its Study 72–75 (Dobbs Ferry, N.Y.: Oceana Publishing 1960)
Llewellyn, Karl N., The Common Law Tradition: Deciding Appeals 11–12, 178–235 (Boston: Little, Brown 1960).
Kripke, Saul A., Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language: An Elementary Exposition (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press 1982)
Radin, Margaret Jane, Reconsidering the Rule of Law, 69 B.U. L. Rev. 781, 797–811 (1989)
Westen, Peter, The Logic of Consent: The Diversity and Deceptiveness of Consent as a Defense to Criminal Conduct (Aldershot: Ashgate 2004)
Wertheimer, Alan, Consent to Sexual Relations (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 2003).
Fuller, Lon L., Positivism & Fidelity to Law: A Reply to Professor Hart, 71 Harv. L. Rev. 630, 663–69 (1958).
Bix, Brian H., Natural Law: The Modern Tradition, in Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law 61 (Coleman, Jules and Shapiro, Scott, eds., New York: Oxford University Press 2002)
Perry, Stephen R., Interpretation and Methodology, in Law and Interpretation: Essays in Legal Philosophy 97 (Marmor, Andrei, ed., Oxford: Clarendon Press 1995).