Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Home
  • Print publication year: 2008
  • Online publication date: October 2009

22 - Genetic testing and screening

Summary

Mr. and Mrs. A have recently had a baby son. They are both carriers of cystic fibrosis, although neither has the condition. Although they knew the risks of producing a child with cystic fibrosis, they decided to proceed with a pregnancy and now wish to know not only if their son has cystic fibrosis but also if he is a carrier.

Mrs. B attends her general practitioner wanting to be referred for a test for predisposition to breast cancer. Her mother had breast cancer and died at the age of 41. She is convinced that because of this family history she also may die prematurely, and she wishes to know the facts in planning her future life.

What is genetic testing and screening?

Although genetic testing and screening have a number of issues in common, they are different in their scope. Genetic “testing” applies to the determination of some genetic factor in an individual, whereas screening aims to ascertain the prevalence of such a factor in a population or population group where there is no evidence in advance that any particular individual has it (Danish Council of Ethics, 1993; Nuffield Council on Bioethics, 1993, 2006; Chadwick, 1998). Genetic testing is normally an issue when either an individual requests it, for example because of knowledge of a family history, or is referred by a medical practitioner. Screening programs, although they will involve actual testing of individuals, are typically part of a public health program, for example in response to a governmentdetermined need to address a given health issue.

REFERENCES
Chadwick, R. (1998). Genetic screening. In The Concise Encyclopedia of the Ethics of New Technologies, ed. Chadwick, R.. San Diego, CA: Academic Press, pp. 193–8.
Chadwick, R. (2004). Nutrigenomics, individualism and public health. Proc Nutr Soc 63: 161–6.
Chadwick, R., Levitt, M., and Shickle, D. (eds.) (1997). The Right to Know and the Right not to Know. Aldershot: Avebury.
Clarke, A. (ed.) (1998). The Genetic Testing of Children, Oxford: Bios Scientific.
Council of Europe (1997). The Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Dignity of the Human Being with Regard to the Application of Biology and Medicine. Brussels: Council of Europe.
Cutter, A. M., Wilson, S., and Chadwick, R. (2004). Balancing powers. J Int Biotechnol Law 1: 187–9.
Danish Council of Ethics (1993). Ethics and Mapping of the Human Genome. Copenhagen: Danish Council of Ethics.
European Group on Ethics in Science and New Technologies (2003). Ethical Aspects of Genetic Testing in the Workplace. Brussels: European Commission.
Fargher, E. A., Eddy, C., Payne, K., et al. (2006). Exploring patients' and healthcare professionals' views of pharmacogenetic testing. In From Genes to Patients: New Perspectives on Personalised Medicines. Warwick University, 5 July, symposium poster.
Food Ethics Council (2005). Getting Personal. Brighton: Food Ethics Council.
Genetic Interest Group (1998). Confidentiality Guidelines. London: Genetic Interest Group.
Häyry, M., Chadwick, R., Arnason, V., and Arnason, G. (eds.) (2007). The Ethics and Governance of Human Genetic Databases: European Perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 11–13, 43–87.
Human Genetics Commission (2003). Inside Information: Balancing Interests in the Use of Personal Genetic Data. London: Department of Health.
Human Genome Organisation (HUGO) Ethics Committee (1996). Statement on the Principled Conduct of Genetic Research. London: HUGO.
Human Genome Organisation (HUGO) Ethics Committee (1998). Statement on DNA Sampling, Control and Access. London: HUGO.
Knoppers, B. and Chadwick, R. (2005). Human genetic research: emerging trends in ethics. Nat Rev Genet 6: 75–9.
Nuffield Council on Bioethics (1993). Genetic Screening: Ethical Issues.London: Nuffield Council on Bioethics.
Nuffield Council on Bioethics (2002). Genetics and Human Behaviour: The Ethical Context. London: Nuffield Council on Bioethics.
Nuffield Council on Bioethics (2003). Pharmacogenomics: Ethical Issues. London: Nuffield Council on Bioethics.
Nuffield Council on Bioethics (2006). Genetic Screening: A Supplement to the 1993 Report by the Nuffield Council on Bioethics. London: Nuffield Council on Bioethics.
Parker, M. and Lucassen, A. (2004). Genetic information: a joint account? BMJ 329: 165–7.
Roses, A. D. (2004). Pharmacogenetics and drug development: the path to safer and more effective drugs. Nat Rev Genet 5: 645–56.
Royal College of Physicians with the Royal College of Pathologists and the British Society for Human Genetics (2006). Consent and Confidentiality in Genetic Practice: Guidance on Genetic Testing and Sharing Genetic Information. A Report of the Joint Committee on Medical Genetics. London: Royal College of Physicians of London.
UK Government and Association of British Insurers (2005). Concordat and Moratorium on Genetics and Insurance. London: Department of Health.
UK National Screening Committee (2003). Criteria for Appraising the Viability, Effectiveness and Appropriateness of a Screening Programme. London: The Stationery Office.
UNESCO (1997). The Universal Declaration on the Human Genome and Human Rights, 11 November. New York: United Nations.