Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-c47g7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-25T02:18:23.309Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

1 - Positivist thought in the nineteenth century

from 1 - Positivism, Idealism, and Pragmatism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 March 2008

Rom Harré
Affiliation:
Georgetown University
Thomas Baldwin
Affiliation:
University of York
Get access

Summary

INTRODUCTION

The positivist impulse, to accept only what is certain and to reject anything in any degree speculative, from its earliest intimations in classical Greece to its most recent revival in contemporary anti-realist philosophy of science, expresses itself in two main ways. It appears as a doctrine about the limits of what human beings can legitimately claim to know, displayed as an austere epistemological attitude. This leads to a foundationalism according to which only what is immediately given by the senses can be known for certain. It also appears as a doctrine about what can legitimately be taken to exist, displayed as an austere ontological attitude. This leads to a scepticism about the existence of unobservables of all sorts, from God to the material substance thought by many philosophers and scientists to account for common experience. Positivism is at root driven by an impulse, attitude, or frame of mind, which expresses itself in a variety of philosophical theses and arguments. That positivistic arguments and analyses are found convincing has perhaps more to do with an attitude of austerity and scepticism, than with their intrinsic worth. Always ready to wield Ockham’s Razor against the proliferation of kinds of entities which people are tempted to believe in, positivists could be said to hold that it is better to accept less than one perhaps could, for fear of believing more than perhaps one should.

The topic of this chapter, the rise of positivism in the nineteenth century, picks out just one of the high points of a repeated cycle of waxing and waning enthusiasm for positivist austerity. Harsher and more relaxed attitudes to what one should reasonably believe have come and gone since antiquity. In the sixteenth century the debates about astronomy turned on an opposition between positivism and realism in science. Should one believe in the reality of the heliocentric theory or was it just a convenient calculating device for predicting the comings and goings of ‘lights in the sky’?

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2003

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Austeda, F. (1967). ‘Avenarius’, trans. Blumberg, A. E.. In Edwards, P. (ed.), The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Avenarius, R. (1888–90). Kritik der reinen Erfahrung (Critique of Pure Experience), Leipzig: O.R. Reisland.Google Scholar
Blackmore, J. T. (1995). Ludwig Boltzmann; his Later Life and Philosophy, Dordrecht and London: Kluwer.Google Scholar
Cahan, D. (1993). Herman von Helmholtz and the Foundations of Nineteenth Century Science, Berkeley and London: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Charlton, D. G. (1959). Positivist Thought in France during the Second Empire: 1852–1870, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Comte, A. (1830–42). Cours de Philosophie Positive, Paris: Baillière. Trans. (in part) 1853 Martineau, H., The Positive Philosophy of Auguste Comte, London: Chapman.Google Scholar
Comte, A. (1852). Catéchisme Posìtiviste, Paris. Trans. 1858 Congreve, R., The Catechism of Positive Religion, London: Chapman.Google Scholar
Haeckel, E. H. P. A. (1874). Anthropogenie oder Entwicklungsgeschichte des Menschen, Leipzig: W. Engelmann. Trans. 1905 McCabe, J., The Evolution of Man, London: Watts.Google Scholar
Haeckel, E. H. P. A. (1899). Die Weltrathsel, Bonn: Strauss. Trans. 1900 McCabe, J., The Riddle of the Universe, London: Watts.Google Scholar
Hegel, G. W. F. (1830). Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse, II: Naturphilosophie, Heidelberg: Winter. Trans. 1970 Miller, A. V., The Philosophy of Nature, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hertz, H. R. (1894). Die Prinzipien der Mechanik. Trans. 1899 Jones, D. E. and Whalley, J. T., The Principles of Mechanics, London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Huxley, T. H. (1863). Evidence as to Man’s Place in Nature, London: Williams and Norgate.Google Scholar
Lenin, V. I. (1920). Materialism and Empirio-criticism, London: Martin Lawrence.Google Scholar
Mach, E. (1883). Die Mechanik in ihrer Entwicklung historisch-critisch dergestellt, Prague. Trans. 1893 McCormack, T. J., The Science of Mechanics, Chicago: Open Court.Google Scholar
Mach, E. (1886 [1906]). Die Analyse der Empfindungen, 5th edn, Jena. Trans. 1914 Williams, C. M. and Waterlow, J., The Analysis of Sensations, Chicago: Open Court.Google Scholar
Mach, E. (1894). Populärwissenschaftliche Vorlesungen, Leipzig: J. A. Borth. Trans. 1894 McCormack, T. J., Popular Scientific Lectures, Chicago: Open Court.Google Scholar
Mill, J. S. (1843). A System of Logic, Ratiocinative and Inductive, 5th edn 1862, London: John Parker.Google Scholar
Passmore, J. (1957). A Hundred Years of Philosophy, London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
Paulsen, F. (1893). ‘Wesen und geschichtliche entwicklung der deutschen universitaten’ in Lexis, W. (ed.), Die deutschen universitaten, Berlin: A. Asher. Trans. 1895 Perry, E. D., The German Universities: Their Character and Historical Development.Google Scholar
Pearson, K. (1892). The Grammar of Science, London: Walter Scott.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1892). Review of ‘The Grammar of Science’, Nation 55.Google Scholar
Spencer, H. (1862–96). System of Synthetic Philosophy vols. I–VI, London: Williams and Norgate.Google Scholar
Spencer, H. (1862). First Principles, vol I of Spencer (1862–96). Repr. 1996, London: Routledge and Thoemmes.Google Scholar
Taine, H. (1864). Le Positivisme Anglais, Paris: Baillière. Trans. 1870 Haye, T. D., English Positivism, London: Simpkin, Marshall and Co.Google Scholar
Taine, H. (1865). Philosophie de l'ArtParis: Baillière. Trans. 1865, Taine, , The Philosophy of Art, London: Baillière.Google Scholar
Turner, R. S. (1980). ‘Helmholtz’, Dictionary of Scientific Biography, vol. V, New York: Scribners.Google Scholar
Whewell, W. (1847). The Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences, 2nd edn, London: Parker, J. W.. Repr. 1967, ed. Herival, J., New York and London: Johnson Reprint Corporation.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×