Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-wq2xx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-23T17:05:32.459Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

19 - Change, time, and place

from III - Natural philosophy

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 May 2011

Robert Pasnau
Affiliation:
University of Colorado Boulder
Get access

Summary

For Aristotle, the natural world is the world of things subject to change. Accordingly, Aristotle’s natural philosophy essentially consists in a philosophical investigation of change. Aristotle deals with the most fundamental philosophical issues about change in the Physics. Here he determines the intrinsic constituents of a thing that make it possible for it to be subject to change (matter and form), he classifies the types of explanatory factor at work in the natural world (the distinction of the four causes), and in particular he argues for the claim that nature acts for an end (teleological explanation). He also gives a general definition of change, which relates the notion of change to the more basic notions of act and potency, he shows that every change is continuous, and he proves the existence of an eternal motion and an unmoved mover. In addition, he provides a philosophical treatment of the notions of time, place, the void, and the infinite, which are thought to be necessary parts of a complete discussion of change. Because of its extremely rich philosophical content, the Physics was intensely studied by medieval philosophers and became the focal text for the assimilation of Aristotle’s natural philosophy.

The Physics was first made available to the Latin world in the second quarter of the twelfth century, when it was translated into Latin (from the Greek) by James of Venice. It circulated quite slowly, however, and so it was only around the middle of the thirteenth century that the Physics started to be widely studied. This is shown by the high number of extant works devoted specifically to the Physics – that is, commentaries on it – from the 1250s onward.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2009

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Dod, Bernard, “Aristoteles Latinus,” in Kretzmann, N. et al. (eds.) The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982).Google Scholar
Donati, Silvia, “Per lo studio dei commenti alla Fisica del XIII secolo. I: Commenti di probabile origine inglese degli anni 1250–1270 ca.,”Documenti e studi sulla tradizione filosofica medievale 2 (1991).Google Scholar
Grant, Edward, “The Medieval Doctrine of Place: Some Fundamental Problems and Solutions,” in Maierù, A. and Paravicini-Bagliani, A. (eds.) Studi sul XIV secolo in memoria di Anneliese Maier (Rome: Edizioni di Storia e Letteratura, 1981).Google Scholar
Maier, Anneliese, Zwischen Philosophie und Mechanik (Rome: Edizioni di Storia e Letteratura, 1958).Google Scholar
Maier, Anneliese, Metaphysische Hintergründe der Spätscholastischen Naturphilosophie (Rome: Edizioni di Storia e Letteratura, 1955).Google Scholar
Trifogli, Cecilia, Oxford Physics in the Thirteenth Century (ca. 1250–1270) (Leiden: Brill, 2000).Google Scholar
Trifogli, Cecilia, “Thomas Wylton on Motion,”Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 77 (1995).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Trifogli, Cecilia, “Averroes’s Doctrine of Time and its Reception in the Scholastic Debate,” in Porro, P. (ed.) The Medieval Concept of Time (Leiden: Brill, 2001).Google Scholar
Trifogli, Cecilia, “La dottrina del luogo in Egidio Romano,”Medioevo 14 (1988).Google Scholar
Trifogli, Cecilia, “Thomas Wylton on the Immobility of Place,”Recherches de théologie et philosophie médiévales 65 (1998).Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×