Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-lvwk9 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-09-27T17:17:24.513Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

5 - History of Conversation Systems: From Eliza to Eugene Goostman

from PART ONE

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 October 2016

Kevin Warwick
Affiliation:
Coventry University
Huma Shah
Affiliation:
Coventry University
Get access

Summary

In the following sections we consider early artificial conversationalists and implementations of experiments to answer Turing's question can a machine think?. The claim for the first Turing test is asserted by Hugh Loebner, sponsor of the annual Loebner Prize for Artificial Intelligence. The first contest appeared in 1991. However, more than a decade earlier a computer program of a paranoid human confounded psychiatrists: they were not able to distinguish the simulation from a real patient (Heiser et al., 1979).

As we said in the previous chapter, during a practical Turing test, the actual goal of the machine is to provide satisfactory and sustained answers to any questions – in the realm of paranoia, PARRY, the program created by Colby et al. (1971, 1972), served this purpose. Christopher Strachey, a contemporary of Turing and a fellow student at King's College Cambridge, in 1952 wrote an algorithm that generated text intended to express and arouse emotions. It was the first machine to produce digital literature (Wardrip-Fruin, 2005). Here's an example of its output:

DARLING SWEETHEART

YOU ARE MY AVID FELLOW FEELING.

MY AFFECTION CURIOUSLY CLINGS TO YOUR

PASSIONATE WISH.

MY LIKING YEARNS FOR YOUR HEART.

YOU ARE MY WISTFUL SYMPATHY: MY TENDER LIKING.

YOURS BEAUTIFULLY.

The distinguished linguist Noam Chomsky (2008) viewed the linguistic performance of a machine preferable to other ways of improving machine capacity and studying human intelligence. He considered that the Turing test provided a stimulus for two useful lines of research:

  1. (a) improvement of the capacities of machines;

  2. (b) investigating the intellectual properties of a human.

Chomsky believed therefore the imitation game is uncontroversial. He accepted Turing's intention as wanting to learn something about living things through the construction of a thinking machine. Moor (2004) contended that Turing's linguistic measure “is not essential to our knowledge about computer thinking … it provides one good format for gathering evidence” so that if a machine were to succeed against Turing's satisfactory and sustained response criterion “one would certainly have very adequate grounds for inductively inferring that the computer could think”.

Type
Chapter
Information
Turing's Imitation Game
Conversations with the Unknown
, pp. 69 - 80
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2016

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Block, N. (1981). Psychologism and behaviorism. Philosophical Review, 90 (1), 5–43. Reprinted in The Turing Test: Verbal Behavior as the Hallmark of Intelligence, S. Shieber (ed). MIT Press, pp. 229–266.Google Scholar
Bush, V. (1945). As we may think. The Atlantic Wire. July.
Chomsky, N. (2008). Turing on the “Imitation Game”. In Parsing the Turing Test: Philosophical and Methodological Issues in the Quest for the Thinking Computer, R., Epstein, G., Roberts, and G., Beber (eds). Springer, pp. 103–106.
Colby, K.M.,Weber, S., and Hilf, F.D. (1971). Artificial paranoia. Artificial Intelligence 2, 1–25.Google Scholar
Colby, K.M., Hilf, F.D., Weber, S., and Kraemer, H.C. (1972). Turing-like indistinguishability tests for the validation of a computer simulation of paranoid processes. Artificial Intelligence 3, 199–221.Google Scholar
Demchenko, E. and Veselov, V. (2008). Who fools whom? The great mystification or methodological issues in making fools of human beings. In Parsing the Turing Test: Philosophical and Methodological Issues in the Quest for the Thinking Computer, R., Epstein, G., Roberts, and G., Beber (eds). Springer, pp 447–459.
Heiser, J.F., Colby, K.M., Fraught, W.S. and Parkison, R.C. (1979). Can psychiatrists distinguish a computer simulation of paranoia from the real thing? The limitation of Turing-like tests as measures of the adequacy of simulations. Journal of Psychiatric Research 15 (3), 149–162.Google Scholar
Moor, J.H. (2004). An analysis of the Turing test. In The Turing Test: Verbal Behavior as the Hallmark of Intelligence, S., Shieber (ed). MIT Press, pp. 297–306.
Shah, H. (2010). Deception-detection and Machine Intelligence in Practical Turing Tests. PhD thesis, University of Reading.
Shah, H. and Pavlika, V. (2005). Text-based dialogical e-query systems: gimmick or convenience? In Proceedings of the 10th International Conference on Speech and Computers (SPECOM), Patras, Greece, Vol II, pp. 425–428.Google Scholar
Shieber, S.M. (1994). Lessons from a restricted Turing test. Communications of the ACM 37 (6), 70–78.Google Scholar
Turing, A.M. (1950). Computing machinery and intelligence. Mind LIX (236), 433–460.Google Scholar
Veselov, V. (2010). Eugene Goostman the Bot. In Third Colloquium on Conversational Systems, Philadelphia.
Wardrip-Fruin, N. (2005). Playable media and textual instruments. In The Aesthetics of Net Literature, P., Gendolla and J., Schafer (eds). Dichtung Digital (Die Deutsche Bibliothek).
Wallace, R. (2010). Chatbot 3.0. The Third Colloquium on Conversational Systems, Philadelphia.
Weizenbaum, J. (1966). ELIZA – a computer programme for the study of natural language communication between men and machines. Communications of the ACM 9, 6–45.Google Scholar
Zakos, J. (2010). How chatbots outperform humans in enterprise applications. In Third Colloquium on Conversational Systems, Philadelphia.

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×