Logical Modalities from Aristotle to Carnap
Buy print or eBook
[Opens in a new window] The Story of Necessity
Book contents
- Frontmatter
- Contents
- List of Figures and Tables
- List of Contributors
- List of Abbreviations
- Introduction
- 1 Aristotle on the Necessity of the Consequence
- 2 Aristotle on One- Sided Possibility
- 3 Why Does Aristotle Need a Modal Syllogistic?
- 4 Necessity, Possibility, and Determinism in Stoic Thought
- 5 Necessity in Avicenna and the Arabic Tradition
- 6 Modality without the Prior Analytics: Early Twelfth Century Accounts of Modal Propositions
- 7 Ockham and the Foundations of Modality in the Fourteenth Century
- 8 Theological and Scientific Applications of the Notion of Necessity in the Mediaeval and Early Modern Periods
- 9 Locke and the Problem of Necessity in Early Modern Philosophy
- 10 Leibniz's Theories of Necessity
- 11 Leibniz and the Lucky Proof
- 12 Divine Necessity and Kant's Modal Categories
- 13 Charles Sanders Peirce on Necessity
- 14 The Development of C. I. Lewis's Philosophy of Modal Logic
- 15 Carnap's Modal Predicate Logic
- Bibliography
- Index
- References
Bibliography
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 05 September 2016
Book contents
- Frontmatter
- Contents
- List of Figures and Tables
- List of Contributors
- List of Abbreviations
- Introduction
- 1 Aristotle on the Necessity of the Consequence
- 2 Aristotle on One- Sided Possibility
- 3 Why Does Aristotle Need a Modal Syllogistic?
- 4 Necessity, Possibility, and Determinism in Stoic Thought
- 5 Necessity in Avicenna and the Arabic Tradition
- 6 Modality without the Prior Analytics: Early Twelfth Century Accounts of Modal Propositions
- 7 Ockham and the Foundations of Modality in the Fourteenth Century
- 8 Theological and Scientific Applications of the Notion of Necessity in the Mediaeval and Early Modern Periods
- 9 Locke and the Problem of Necessity in Early Modern Philosophy
- 10 Leibniz's Theories of Necessity
- 11 Leibniz and the Lucky Proof
- 12 Divine Necessity and Kant's Modal Categories
- 13 Charles Sanders Peirce on Necessity
- 14 The Development of C. I. Lewis's Philosophy of Modal Logic
- 15 Carnap's Modal Predicate Logic
- Bibliography
- Index
- References
Summary
A summary is not available for this content so a preview has been provided. Please use the Get access link above for information on how to access this content.
- Type
- Chapter
- Information
- Logical Modalities from Aristotle to CarnapThe Story of Necessity, pp. 317 - 338Publisher: Cambridge University PressPrint publication year: 2016
References
2014, “Kant's Only Possible Argument and Chignell's Real Harmony,” Kantian Review
19(1), 1–25.Google Scholar
, 1970, Petrus Abaelardus, Dialectica, 2nd ed., ed. , Assen: Van Gorcum, Tract. II.2, 191–210.
2010, “Petrus Abaelardus, Glossae Super Peri Hermenias,”
in Corpus Christianorum Continuatio Mediaevalis
206, ed. and
Brepols: Turnhout, cap. 12, 391–433.
1963, Aristotle's Categories and De Interpretatione, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
, 1964–1976, (AT), Oeuvres de Descartes, 11 vols., Paris: J. Vrin.
and , 1973, “Did Ockham Know of Material and Strict Implication,” Franciscan Studies
33, 5–37.Google Scholar
1994. Leibniz: Determinist, Theist, Idealist, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
, 1983, Ockham, William, Predestination, God's Foreknowledge and Future Contingents, tr. with intro by and 2nd edition, Hackett Classics.
, and , 1924, Kant und das Ding an Sich, Berlin: Pan Verlag.
, Alexander of Aphrodisias, 1883, On Aristotle's Prior Analytics, ed. , in Diels, 1882–1909, Vol. 2.1.
Alexander of Aphrodisias 1892, On Fate. ed. , Supplementum Aristotelicum, Vol. 2.2, Berlin: Reimer.
Alexander of Aphrodisias 1991, On Aristotle's Topics. ed. , in Diels 1882–1909, Vol. 2.2.
2004, “Kant's ‘One World’: Interpreting Transcendental Idealism,” British Journal for the History of Philosophy
12, 655–684.Google Scholar
, 1983, Kant's Transcendental Idealism, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. (2004). Revised and Enlarged Edition.
, 1994, “Causality and Causal Laws in Kant: A Critique of Michael Friedman” in Parrini, P. (1994), 291–307.
1996, Logical Reasoning with Diagrams, Oxford University Press.
and , ed., 1982, “Recent Work on Kant's Theoretical Philosophy,” The Philosophical Quarterly
19, 1–24.Google Scholar
, 2003, Interpreting Kant's Three Critiques. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
1897, Ammonius in Aristotelis De Interpretatione Commentarius, ed. , in Diels, 1882–1909, Vol. 4.5.
, 1975, Entailment: Logic of Relevance and Necessity, Vol. I. Princeton University Press.
, and , 2004, “It Adds Up After All: Kant's Philosophy of Arithmetic in Light of the Traditional Logic,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research
69, 501–540.Google Scholar
, 1979, “The Aristotelian Modal Syllogistic in Modern Modal Logic,” in Konstruktionen versus Positionen II (P. Lorenzen zum 60. Geburtstag), ed. , Berlin: de Gruyter, 176–215.
, Anselm of Canterbury, 1936, “Ein neues unvollendetes Werk des hl. Anselm von Canterbury,” Beiträge zur Geschichte der Philosophie und Theologie des Mittelalters
33(3), 23–48.
1968, Anselmi Cantuariensis Archiepiscopi Opera Omnia, ed. , Stuttgart: Friedrich Fromann Verlag.
2011, John Locke and Natural Philosophy, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
, (forthcoming) “Locke and non-propositional knowledge.”
1979, ““Things in Themselves: Intentionality and Reality in Kant,” Archiv Fur Geschichte der Philosophie
61, 293–307.Google Scholar
, 1985, The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation, ed. , 2 vols., Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
, 1994, Posterior Analytics, Translated with an Introduction and Commentary by Jonathan Barnes, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 2nd ed.
1998, Aristotle, Metaphysics, trans. and with an introduction and commentary by , Clarendon Aristotle Series Oxford: Clarendon Press.
2009, Aristote, Topiques tome I, livres I-IV ed. , Paris: Les belles lettres.
1996, Logic or the Art of Thinking, trans. , Cambridge University Press.
and , Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta, Vols. I-IV. Leipzig: Teubner. 1902.
, 1974, Language and Logic in the Post-Medieval Period, Dordrecht: D. Reidel.
, 2001, “Petrus Abaelardus on Modalities de re and de dicto,” Potentialität und Possibilität: Modalaussagen in der Geschichte der Metaphysik, ed. , Stuttgart: Frommann-Holzboog, 79–95.
, 1562. Quaesita octo in librum Priorum, in Aristotelis omnia quae extant opera – Averrois Cordubensis in ea opera omnes, qui ad haec usque tempora peruenere, commentarii (Venetiis apud Iunctas).
(Ibn Ruṣd), 1954, Tah al-tah: The Incoherence of the “Incoherence,” trans. , 2 vols., Oxford University Press.
1977, Liber de philosophia prima sive scientia divina ed. , Louvain: E. Peters.
(Ibn Sīnā), 1984, Remarks and Admonitions [Pointers and Reminders] translated from the original Arabic with an introduction and notes by , Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies.
2004, The Metaphysics of the Healing, trans. , Provo, Utah: Brigham Young University Press.
2011, Deliverance Logic, trans. (Oxford University Press).
2004, The Instauratio magna Part II: Novum organum and Associated Texts, Oxford Francis Bacon, trans. and ed. , Vol. XI, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
, 1978, “Cléanthe et Chrysippe face au maitre-argument de Diodore,” in Brunschwig 1978, 20–41.
, 1734, The Usefulness of Mathematical Learning, trans. , London: Stephen Austen.
, 1933, Die Aristotelische Theorie der Möglichkeitsschlüsse, Berlin: Junker und Dünnhaupt.
, 1930, “Zur Logic der Modalitäten,” Jahrbuch fur Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung
11, 497–548.Google Scholar
, 2002. “Leibniz on Wachter's Elucidarius cabalisticus: A Critical Edition of the So-Called ‘Refutation of Spinoza.’” The Leibniz Review
12, 1–14.Google Scholar
, 2009, Doing and Being: An Interpretation of Aristotle's Metaphysics Theta, Oxford University Press [Oxford Aristotle Series].
, 2002, German Idealism: The Struggle against Subjectivism 1781–1801, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
, 2000, “Infallibility and Modal Knowledge in Some Early Modern Philosophers,” in Mathematics and Necessity: Essays in the History of Philosophy, ed. , Oxford: Oxford University Press, 139–166.
, 1962, Kant's Theory of Knowledge, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
, 2012, “Indexical Hybrid Tense Logic,” in Advances in Modal Logic, London: King's College, 144–160.
, and , 1963, “On the Interpretation of Aristotle, De Interpretatione 12–13,” Classical Quarterly
13, 214–222.Google Scholar
, 1988. “Freedom, Contingency, and Things Possible in Themselves.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research
49(1): 81–101. doi:10.2307/2107993.Google Scholar
, 1617, The Arte of Logick, London [1st edition 1599].
, 1986, Die stoische Modallogik. Königshausen & Neumann.
, 1993, “Chrysippus’ modal logic and its relation to Philo and Diodorus,” in and Th. Ebert (eds) Dialektiker und Stoiker, Stuttgart, 63–84.
1999, “Logic: The Megarics, the Stoics,” in The Cambridge History of Hellenistic Philosophy, ed. , . , , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 83–157.
2003, “Stoic Logic,” in The Cambridge Companion to the Stoics, ed. , Cambridge University Press, 85–123.
1951, Ancient Formal Logic, Amsterdam: North-Holland.
, 1877, Commentarii in Librum Aristotelis Peri Hermenias, ed. , Leipzig: Teubner.
, 1969, De Hypotheticis Syllogismis, ed. , Brescia: Paidea.
2008, De Syllogismo Categorico, ed. , Gothenburg: University of Gothenburg.
1870, Index Aristotelicus, Berlin: Reimer.
, 1999–2000, Works: The Works of Robert Boyle, ed. and , 14 vols., London: Pickering and Chatto.
, 2006, Boyle on Atheism, transcribed by and ed. , Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
2011, “On Composite Systems: Descartes, Newton, and the Law-Constitutive Approach,” in Vanishing Matter and the Laws of Motion: Descartes and Beyond, ed. and , New York: Routledge, 130–152.
, 2012, “Newton's Law-Constitutive Approach to Bodies: A Response to Descartes,” in Interpreting Newton: Critical Essays, ed. and , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 13–32.
,
1998, “Peircean Graphs for the Modal Logic S5,” in Conceptual Structures: Theory, Tools and Applications, ed. and , Berlin and Heidelberg: Springer, 255–269.
, 2006, “Hybrid Logic,” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logic-hybrid/.
1994, “Two Modal Theses in the Second Half of Metaphysics Theta 4.” Phronesis
39, 160–173.Google Scholar
, 1987. “Compossibility, Harmony, and Perfection in Leibniz.” The Philosophical Review
96(2), 173–203.Google Scholar
, 1969, “La proposition particulière et les preuves de non-concluance chez Aristote,” Cahiers pour l'Analyse
10, 3–26.Google Scholar
, 1978, Les stoïciens et leur logique. Vrin. Second edition 2006.
1994, Die Modallogik des Aristoteles in den Analytica Priora A, Hildesheim: Olms.
, 1994, “Game-Theoretical Semantics for Peirce's Existential Graphs,” Synthese
99, 361–375.Google Scholar
, 1981, “Aristotle on Understanding Knowledge,” in Aristotle on Science: The Posterior Analytics, Proceedings of the Eighth Symposium Aristotelicum held in Pisa from September 2 to 15, 1978, E. Berti, ed., Padua: Antenore, 97-139.
, 1937, The Logical Syntax of Language, London: Kegan Paul, Trench Truber.
, 1947, Meaning and Necessity, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Second edition 1956, references are to the second edition.
1950, “Empiricism, Semantics and Ontology,” Revue Intern de Phil
4, 20–40. Reprinted in the second edition of Carnap 1947, 205–221. Page references are to this reprint.Google Scholar
1952, “Meaning Postulates,” Philosophical Studies
3, 65–73. Reprinted in the second edition of Carnap 1947, 222–229. Page references are to this reprint.Google Scholar
1955, “Meaning and Synonymy in Natural Languages,” Philosophical Studies
7. Reprinted in the second edition of Carnap 1947, 233–250. Page references are to this reprint.Google Scholar
1963, “Carnap's Intellectual Biography,” The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap, ed. , La Salle, IL: Open Court, 3–84.
,
2009, “Kant, Modality, and the Most Real Being,” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie
91(2), 157–192.Google Scholar
2010, “Real Repugnance and Belief about Things in Themselves: A Problem and Kant's Three Solutions,” in Kant's Moral Metaphysics, ed. and , Berlin: Walter DeGruyter.
2012, “Kant, Real Possibility, and the Threat of Spinoza,” The Monist
121(483), 635–675.Google Scholar
2014, “Kant and the ‘Monstrous’ Ground of Possibility: A Reply to Abaci and Yong.” Kantian Review, 19(1), 53–69.Google Scholar
1975, De divinatione; De fato; Timaeus, ed. , Leipzig: Teubner.
, 1933, On the Nature of the Gods, Academica, trans. , London: Heinemann.
1692, The Principles of the Most Ancient and Modern Philosophy, trans. J. C. ( ?), London.
, 1984–1991, The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, 3 vols., Vols. I and II, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985, and Vol. III, The Correspondence, by the same translators plus A. Kenny, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991.
, and , trans., 2013, “Carnap and Mckinsey: Topics in the Pre-History of Possible Worlds Semantics,” Proceedings of the 12th Asian Logic Conference, ed. , , and
Singapore: World Scientific, 53–75.
, 2014, “The Completeness of Carnap's Predicate Logic,” Australasian Journal of Logic
11, 47–63.Google Scholar
2004, Aristotle on Truth, Cambridge: Cambridge Universit Press.
, 1678, The True Intellectual System of the Universe, London: Richard Royston.
, 1996, A Treatise Concerning Eternal and Immutable Morality, ed. , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Circa 1664, 1st ed. 1731.
2014, “Descartes’ modal metaphysics,” The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, Spring 2014 ed., ed. Edward N. Zalta, URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/descartes-modal/>
, 1984, “Descartes on the Creation of the Eternal Truths,” The Philosophical Review
93, 569–597.Google Scholar
, 1743, Traité de dynamique, Paris.
, 2015, “How Nothing Can Be Something: The Stoic Theory of Void,” Ancient Philosophy 35, 405-29.
, ,
1985. The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, ed. , , , and , 3 vols., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
, 1996. Oeuvres de Descartes, ed. and , 11 vols., Paris: J. Vrin.
1882–1909, Commentaria in Aristotelem Graeca, Berlin: Reimer.
, ed., 1964, Diogenis Laertii Vitae Philosphorum, ed. , Oxford Classical Texts, 2 vols., Oxford: Clarendon Press.
, ,
1992, “Are Corpuscles Unobservable in Principle for Locke?,” Journal of the History of Philosophy
30, 33–52.Google Scholar
, 1624, The Elements of Logick, trans. , London: Printed by I. D. for Nicolas Bourne.
, 2007, Aristoteles: Analytica Priora, Buch I, Berlin: Akademie Verlag.
and , 2009. “Impossible Antecedents and Their Consequences: Some Thirteenth-Century Arabic Discussions,” History and Philosophy of Logic
30, 209–225.Google Scholar
, 1916, Epicteti Dissertationes ab Arriano digestae, ed. , Leipzig: Teubner.
, 1878, Kants Kriticismus in der ersten und in der zweiten Auflage der Kritik der reinen Vernunft, Leipzig: Voss.
, ,
1986, Peirce, Semeiotic, and Pragmatism, Bloomington, IN:Hilpinen, Risto (1982, “On C. S. Peirce's theory of the proposition: Peirce as a Precursor of Game-Theoretical Semantics), The Monist 62, 182–189.
2011, “Causal and Logical Necessity in Malebranche's Occasionalism,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy
41, 523–548.Google Scholar
, 1998, First-Order Modal Logic, Dordrecht: Kluwer.
and , 1977, “Descartes on the Creation of the Eternal Truths,” The Philosophical Review
86, 36–57.Google Scholar
, ,
1990, “Fatalism and Future Truth,” Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy
6, 195–227.Google Scholar
2003, “Stoic Determinism” in ed.
The Cambridge Companion to the Stoics. Cambridge University Press. 179–205.
1974, Die stoische Logik. Vandenhoeck und Ruprecht.
, 1989, Two New Sciences, Including Centers of Gravity and Force of Gravity and Force of Percussion, Toronto, Wall and Thompson.
, 1992, “Treatise on Demonstration,” trans. in Galileo's Logical Treatises, Dordrecht: Kluwer.
1959, Dialectica, ed. , Assen: Van Gorcum.
, ( ), 1489, Determinationes Magistrales, Rome.
, 1981, Institutio Logica, trans. [1658], Assen: van Gorcum.
, 1968, Aulus Gellius Noctes Atticae, ed. , Oxford Classical Texts, Vols. 1–2, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
, Conceivability and Possibility, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
, and , eds. 1995. Kurt Gödel: Collected Works. Vol. III. Unpublished Essays and Lectures, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
, and , 1970, Collected Papers of Clarence Irving Lewis, Stanford University Press, (cited as CP).
, and , eds., 1936, Die Entstehung der Aristotelischen Logik, Berlin: Junker und Dünnhaupt.
, 2000, La Dialectique des Stoïciens, Vrin.
, Gregory of Rimini, Gregorii Ariminensis OESA Lectura super Primum et Secundum Sententiarum ed. et al., Berlin and New York: Walter de Gruyter.
Gregory of Rimini 1981, Tomus I: Super Primum (Dist. 1–6).
Gregory of Rimini 1982, Tomus II: Super Primum (Dist. 17–17).
Gregory of Rimini 1984, Tomus III: Super Primum (Dist. 19–48).
Gregory of Rimini 1979a, Tomus IV: Super Secundum (Dist. 1–5).
Gregory of Rimini 1979b, Tomus V: Super Secundum (Dist. 6–18).
Gregory of Rimini 1980, Tomus VI: Super Secundum (Dist. 24–44).
Gregory of Rimini 1987, Tomus VII: Indices.
2013. Leibniz, God and Necessity, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
, 1912, Die Philosophishen Werke des Robert Grossetest: Bischofs von Lincoln, Beitraäge zur Geschichte de Philosophie des Mittelalters, ed , 9, Münster. W.
, ,
1980, “Proof and Eternal Truths: Descartes and Leibniz,” in , ed., Descartes: Philosophy, Mathematics and Physics, Sussex: The Harvester Press.
1999, “Determinism and Indeterminism” in eds. , . , . The Cambridge History of Hellenistic Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. 1999. 513–541.
, 2006, Kant, Science, and Human Nature. Oxford University Press.
, 1977, Semiotics and Signifies: The Correspondence between Charles S. Peirce and Victoria Lady Welby. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
(ed.), 2000, “Infinite Analysis and the Problem of the Lucky Proof,” Studia Leibnitiana
XXXII(2), 151–165.Google Scholar
and , ,
1982, “On C. S. Peirce's Theory of the Proposition: Peirce as a Precursor of Game-Theoretical Semantics,” The Monist
62, 182–189.Google Scholar
1969, Models for Modalities: Selected Essays, Dordrecht: Reidel.
, 1973, Time and Necessity: Studies in Aristotle's Theory of Modality, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
1977, Aristotle on Modality and Determinism, in collaboration with and , Acta Philosophica Fennica 29.1, Amsterdam: North Holland.
1997, “The Place of C. S. Peirce in the History of Logical Theory,” in The Rule of Reason, ed. and , Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 140–161.
2010, “Ibn Sīnā on understood time and aspect (Qiyās 1.3),” http://wilfridhodges.co.uk/arabic08.pdf.
, 2012a, “Ibn Sīnā's modal logic,” http://wilfridhodges.co.uk/arabic20a.pdf slide 31.
2012b, Translation of Ibn Ruṣd, Mas'ala i.3 p.122, in (Hodges, “Handout for ‘Necessary and permanent in Ibn Sīnā’,” http://wilfridhodges.co.uk/arabic20b.pdf.
2014, Mathematical Background to the Logic of Ibn Sīnā Draft, http://wilfridhodges.co.uk/arabic44.pdf.
1985, Peirce, London: Routledge.
, 2008, “Pragmatism and the Given: C. I. Lewis, Quine, and Peirce” in The Oxford Handbook of American Philosophy, ed. , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
1973, “Greek Grice: A Brief Survey of Proto-Conversational Rules in the History of Logic,” Proceedings of the Chicago Linguistic Society
9, 205–214.Google Scholar
, 1989, A Natural History of Negation, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
1997, Studies in the Logic of Charles Sanders Peirce, Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
and , , eds., 2002, “Did Aristotle Reply to Eudemus and Theophrastus on Some Logical Issues?” In Eudemus of Rhodes, Rutgers University Studies in Classical Humanities, Vol. 11, ed. and , New Brunswick:Transaction, 85–106.
, 1902, An Enquiry Concerning the Human Understanding, Ed. , Oxford, Clarendon Press.
, 1999–2000, The Works of Robert Boyle, ed., 14 vols., London: Pickering and Chatto.
, and , 1997, Hellenistic Philosophy, Introductory Readings, Indianapolis: Hackett. 1988. 1997.
, and , 1990. Leibniz's Philosophy of Logic and Language, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
, 1999, Squaring the Circle: the War Between Hobbes and Wallis, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
, 2013, “Logic and Demonstrative Knowledge,” in , ed., The Oxford Handbook of British Philosophy in the Seventeenth Century, Oxford University Press,373–390.
1989, “Models for Modal Syllogisms,” Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic
30(2), 271–284.Google Scholar
, 1995, “Apodeictic Syllogisms: Deductions and Decision Procedures,” History and Philosophy of Logic
16(1), 1–18.Google Scholar
1900-, Kants gesammelte Schriften, ed. the Berlin- Brandenburg (formerly Royal Prussian) Academy of Sciences, Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.
, 1992, Theoretical Philosophy 1775–1770, trans. and ed. and , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
1996, Religion and Rational Theology, trans. and ed., and , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
1997, Critique of Pure Reason, trans. and ed. and , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
1972, “
Possible and Must,” in Syntax and Semantics, ed. , vol. 1, New York: Academic Press, 1–20.
, ,
2015, “Pseudo-Joscelin: The Treatise on Genera and Species,” Oxford Studies in Medieval Philosophy
2, 104–211.Google Scholar
, 1937, “Logical and Metaphysical Necessity,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society. Harrison & Sons, 253–268.
, 1962, The Development of Logic. Oxford University Press. 1962.
, and , 1980, “Time and Modality in Scholasticism,” in ed. Reforging the Great Chain of Being, Dordrecht: Reidel, 163–257.
, 1972, Naming and Necessity, Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.
, ,
2007, “Peirce's Modal Shift: From Set Theory to Pragmaticism,” Journal of the History of Philosophy
45(4), 551–576.Google Scholar
, 1998, Kantian Humility, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
, ,
2008, “The Problem of the Essential Icon,” American Philosophical Quarterly
45(3), 207–232.Google Scholar
, 2012, “The Hardness of the Iconic Must: Can Peirce's Existential Graphs Assist Modal Epistemology?,” Philosophia Mathematica
20(1), 1–24.Google Scholar
2014, “Things Unreasonably Compulsory”: A Peircean Challenge to a Human Theory of Perception, Particularly with Respect to Perceiving Necessary Truths,” Cognitio
15(1), 89–112.Google Scholar
1961. Die philosophischen Schriften von Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, ed. , Berlin: Weidman. [Hildesheim: Georg Olms, 1961, Authors who cite Leibniz 1961 are referring to this reprint]
, 1875–1890, 1903, Opuscules et Fragments Inédits de Leibniz, ed. , Paris: Félix Alcan.
1923-. Sämtliche Schriften und Briefe, ed. Deutsche Akademie der Wissenschaften zu Berlin, Darmstadt and Berlin: Akademie Verlag.
1948, Textes inédits: d'après les manuscrits de la Bibliothèque provincale de Hanovre. ed. , 2 vols., Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.
1966, Logical Papers: A Selection, ed. , Oxford: Clarendon Press.
1969, Philosophical Papers and Letters, ed. , 2nd ed., Dordrecht: Reidel.
1981, New Essays on Human Understanding, and , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
1981a, Theodicy, trans. , La Salle: Open Court, 1985.
New Essays on Human Understanding, trans. and ed. and , Cambridge University Press.
1985, Theodicy, trans. , La Salle, IL: Open Court.
1989, Philosophical Essays, ed. and , Indianapolis: Hackett.
1992, De Summa Rerum: Metaphysical Papers, 1675–76, ed. , New Haven, CT: Yale Univ. Press.
1995, Philosophical Writings, ed. and , London: Everyman.
1996, New Essays on Human Understanding, ed. and , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
2006, Confessio Philosophi: Papers Concerning the Problem of Evil, 1671–1678, ed. , New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
1983, Pragmatics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
, ,
1912b, “Naturalism and Idealism,” University of California Chronicle, 14, 192–211. Reprinted in Lewis 1970.Google Scholar
1913, “Interesting Theorems in Symbolic Logic,” Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods
10, 239–342.Google Scholar
1913b, “A New Algebra of Implications and Some Consequences,” Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods
10, 428–438.Google Scholar
1914, “The Matrix Algebra for Implications,” The Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods
11, 589–600.Google Scholar
1916, “Types of Order and the System Σ,” The Philosophical Review
25, 407– 419. Reprinted in Lewis 1970, 360–370.Google Scholar
1917, “The Issues Concerning Material Implication,” The Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods
14, 350–356.Google Scholar
1918, A Survey of Symbolic Logic, Berkeley, University of California Press, first edition.
1920, “Strict Implication – an Emendation,” The Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods
17, 300–302.Google Scholar
1921, “The Structure of Logic and Its Relation to Other Systems,” The Journal of Philosophy
18, 505–516. Reprinted in Lewis 1970, pp 371–382.Google Scholar
1923, “Facts, Systems, and the Unity of the World,” The Journal of Philosophy
20, 141–151. Reprinted in Lewis 1970, pp 383–393.Google Scholar
1923b, “A Pragmatic Conception of the A Priori,” The Journal of Philosophy
20, 169–177. Reprinted in Lewis 1970, pp 231–239.Google Scholar
1926, “The Pragmatic Element in Knowledge,” University of California Publications in Philosophy
6, 205–227.Google Scholar
1929, Mind and the World Order: Outline of a Theory of Knowledge, New York: Charles Scribner and Sons.
1932, “Alternative Systems of Logic,” The Monist
17, 481–507. Reprinted in Lewis 1970, pp 400–419.Google Scholar
1946, Analysis of Knowledge and Valuation, LaSalle, IL: Open Court.
1955, “Realism or Phenomenalism?,” The Philosophical Review
64, 233–247. Reprinted in Lewis 1970, pp 335–347.Google Scholar
1968, “Autobiography,” in The Philosophy of C. I. Lewis, ed. , LaSalle, IL: Open Court, 1–21
1970. Collected Papers of Clarence Irving Lewis, ed. and , Jr., Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
1932, Symbolic Logic. New York:
Dover, second edition, 1959 [Note: references to Lewis and Langford 1959, are to the second edition of Lewis and Langford 1932]
, and , 2014, “A Note on Strict Implication,” History and Philosophy of Logic
35, 44–49. The manuscript of this article was written before or in 1935.Google Scholar
and
1973, “Causation,” The Journal of Philosophy 70(17), 556–567.
1986, On the Plurality of Worlds, Oxford: Blackwell.
,
1823, The Works of John Locke, 12th edition, 10 vols., London: Tegg.
, 1975, An Essay concerning Human Understanding, 4th ed., ed. , Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975 [1st edition 1690; 4th edition 1700].
, 1989, Some Thoughts Concerning Education, eds and , Oxford: Clarendon Press.
, 1970, “Stoic Determinism and Alexander of Aphrodisias De Fato (I-Xiv),” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie
52, 247–268.Google Scholar
, 1971, “Freedom and Determinism in the Stoic Theory of Human Action,” Problems in Stoicism. The Athlone Press. 173–199.Google Scholar
, 1987, The Hellenistic Philosophers. Cambridge University Press.
, and , 2006. “Some Remarks on the Ontological Arguments of Gödel and Leibniz,” in Einheit in der Vielheit: Akten des VIII. Internationalen Leibniz-Kongresses, ed. et al., Hanover: Hartmann, 510–517.
, The Oxford Handbook to Leibniz, ed. , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
, (forthcoming) “Leibniz's Arguments for the Existence of God.” In , “
1694, A Discourse Concerning the Nature of Man, London: Walter Kettilby.
, 1957, Aristotle's Syllogistic from the Standpoint of Modern Formal Logic, 2nd ed., Oxford: Clarendon Press.
, 1972. On a Controversial Demonstration of Aristotle's Modal Syllogistic: An Enquiry on Prior Analytics
A.15. Padua.
, 1963. Aristotle's Modal Syllogisms, Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Company.
, 1993, “Theory of Knowledge,” in The Cambridge Companion to Aquinas, eds. and , Cambridge University Press, 160–195.
, ,
1997, “The Argument from the Need for Similar or ‘Higher’ Qualities: Cudworth, Locke, and Clarke on God's Existence,” Enlightenment and Dissent
16, 29–59.Google Scholar
1998a, “Aquinas and Ockham on Time, Predestination and the Unexpected Examination,” Franciscan Studies
55, 181–220.Google Scholar
1998b, “Aquinas on Necessity
,” American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly
72, 470–503.Google Scholar
2006, Boyle on Atheism, transcribed and edited, Toronto, University of Toronto Press.
,
1992, Principles and Proofs: Aristotle's Theory of Demonstrative Science, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
, 1900, Die Syllogistik des Aristoteles II.1: Formenlehre und Technik des Syllogismus, Tübingen: Laupp.
, 1960. “Anselm's Ontological Arguments,” The Philosophical Review 49, 41-62.
, ,
2013, Aristotle's Modal Syllogistic, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
, 2013, “Proof by Assumption of the Possible in Prior Analytics 1. 15,” Mind
122, 953–986.Google Scholar
, and , 1996, Philosophy of Mathematics and Mathematical Practice in the Seventeenth Century, New York: Oxford University Press.
, ,
2014, “A Survey of Lewisian Logic: The Development of C. I. Lewis's Philosophy of Modal Logic,” (This volume).
2009, “Why Play Logical Games?,” Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science
15, 3–26.Google Scholar
, 2001, “Abaelard on Modality, Some Possibilities and Some Puzzles,” in Potentialität und Possibilität: Modalaussagen in der Geschichte der Metaphysik, Stuttgart, ed. et al., Frommann-Holzboog, 97–125.Google Scholar
, 2004, “Logic,” in The Cambridge Companion to Abelard, ed. and
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 158–199.
2009 “The Logical Textbooks and their Influence,” in The Cambridge Companion to Boethius, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009, 56–84.
1953, Stoic Logic. University of California Press.
, 1986. The Philosophy of Leibniz: Metaphysics and Language, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
1999, “The Stoic Theory of Categories”, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, XVII, 215-47.
, 1969, Aristotele: Gli Analitici Primi, Napoli: Loffredo.
, Les stoïciens et leur logique, ed. , Vrin. 1978. 303–332.
“Sur la logique modale des stoïciens,” in 2012, “Locke and the Elements of Natural Philosophy: Some Problems of Attribution,” Intellectual History Review
22, 199–219.Google Scholar
, 1991, Truth and the End of Inquiry: A Peircean Account of Truth, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
, 2013, The American Pragmatists, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Cambridge Pragmatism: The Influence of Peirce and James on Ramsey and Wittgenstein, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
(forthcoming). 1662, An Antidote Against Atheism, in A Collection of Several Philosophical Writings of Dr Henry More, London: William Borden, 2nd ed.
, 1979, “Modality, Analogy, and Ideal Experiments According to C. S. Peirce,” Synthese
41, 65–83.Google Scholar
, 2005, C. I. Lewis: The Last Great Pragmatist, Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
, 2010. “The Harmony of Spinoza and Leibniz,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research
81(1): 64–104.Google Scholar
, 1730, Opticks or a Treatise of the Reflections, Refractions, Inflections and Colours of Light, London: William Innys, 4th ed.
, 1984, “Future Contingents,” in The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy ed. and , Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
, 1993, “The Necessity in Deduction: Cartesian Inference and Its Medieval Background,” Synthese
96, 437–454.Google Scholar
,
1996, Modale Syllogismen, mögliche Welten, Essentialismus: eine Analyse der aristotelischen Modallogik, Berlin and New York: de Gruyter.
2006, “Against Appearances True: On a Controversial Modal Theorem in Metaphysics Theta 4,” Zeitschrift für philosophische Forschung
60: 380–393.Google Scholar
1970,
Scriptum in Librum Primum Sententiarum (Ordinatio)
, in Opera Theologica II, ed. , New York: St. Bonaventure.
, 1974a, Ockham's Theory of Terms, Part I of the Summa Logicae, translated and introduced by , Notre Dame, University of Notre Dame Press.
1974b, Opera philosophica. Vol 1. Summa logicae, St Bonaventure, NY:
Editiones Instituti Franciscani Universitatis S. Bonaventurae.
1978, “
Tractatus de Praedestinatione
,” in Opera Philosophica II, ed. , New York: St. Bonaventure.
1980a, Ockham's Theory of Propositions: Part II of the Summa Logicae, translated by and , introduction by , Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.
1980b, Quodlibeta Septem, ed , Opera Theologica, Vol. 9, St. Bonaventure, NY: The Franciscan Institute.
,
1997, “C. S. Peirce and the Quest for Gamma Graphs” in Conceptual Structures: Fulfilling Peirce's Dream, Berlin and Heidelberg: Springer
357–370.
1995. Ontological Arguments and Belief in God. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
, 1597a, In Porphyrii Isagogen et Aristotelis Organum Commentarius Analyticus, Frankfurt: Heredes Andreae Wecheli.
, 1597b, In Porphyrii Isagogen et Aristotelis Organum Commentarius Analyticus, Frankfurt: Heredes Andreae Wecheli.
1965, Logic and Reality in Leibniz's Metaphysics, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
, 1973, Leibniz, Philosophical Writings, trans. and , London: Dent.
ed., 1994, Kant and Contemporary Epistemology, Dordrecht: Kluwer.
, ed., 1968, “The Logic of C. I. Lewis,” in The Philosophy of C. I. Lewis, ed. , LaSalle, IL: Open Court, 15–54.
Google Scholar
, 1961, A History of Chemistry, 4 vols., London: Macmillan.
, 1954, “
L'Esprit Geometrique
,” in Blaise Pascal, Œuvres Complètes, ed. , Paris: Librairie Gallimard.
1995, Aristotle's Modal Logic: Essence and Entailment in the Organon, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
, 1968, Aristotle's Theory of the Syllogism, (Translated by ), Dordrecht: D. Reidel.
1870, “Description of a Notation for the Logic of Relatives, Resulting from an Amplification of the Conceptions of Boole's Calculus,” Memoirs of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences
9(2), 317–378.Google Scholar
, 1885, “On the Algebra of Logic: A Contribution to the Philosophy of Notation,” American Journal of Mathematics
7(2), 180–196.Google Scholar
1958–1966, The Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. 1–6, ed. and , Vols. 7–8, ed. , Cambridge: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
1976, The New Elements of Mathematics, Vols. 1–3, ed. , Berlin: Mouton.
1976a, The Writings of Charles S. Peirce: A Chronological Edition, ed. , 6 vols., et al. Indianapolis: Peirce Edition Project, Indiana University-Purdue University Indianapolis.
1997, Pragmatism as a Principle and Method of Right Thinking: The 1903 Harvard lectures on pragmatism, ed. : SUNY Press.
1998, The Essential Peirce: Selected Philosophical Writings, Vol. 2 (1893–1913), ed. The Peirce Edition Project, Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
2010, Philosophy of Mathematics: Selected Writings, ed. , Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
n.d. Charles Sanders Peirce Papers, Houghton Library, Harvard University.
2007, “Kant on Transcendental Freedom,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research
73, 537–567.Google Scholar
(2010, “
Nous and Two Kinds of Epistêmê in Aristotle's Posterior Analytics
,” Phronesis
55, 228–254.Google Scholar
, 1968, Philodemus: On the methods of inference, ed. , and , Naples: Bibliopolis. 2nd ed., 1978.
, 2005, “Compositionality, Relevance, and Peirce's Logic of Existential Graphs,” Axiomathes
15(4), 513–540.Google Scholar
, 2006a, “Peirce's Contributions to Possible-Worlds Semantics,” Studia Logica
82(3), 345–369.Google Scholar
2006b, Signs of Logic: Peircean Themes on the Philosophy of Language, Games, and Communication, Dordrecht: Springer.
2008, “Aristotle's Cubes and Consequential Implication,” Logica universalis
2, 143–153.Google Scholar
, 1978. The Nature of Necessity, Cambridge: Clarendon Press.
, 1976a, De communibus notitiis contra Stoicos. Moralia XIII.2. ed. , Cambridge, MA, and London:Loeb.
1976b, De Stoicroum repugnantiis, Moralia XIII.2. ed. , Cambridge, MA, and London:Loeb.
1974, Kant und das Problem der Dinge an Sich, Bonn: Grundman.
, ,
1960, “Identifiable Individuals,” Review of Metaphysics, 13, 684–696. Reprinted in 1968, ch. 7, 66–77.Google Scholar
1967, Past Present and Future, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
1968, Papers on Time and Tense, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
1975,”Is Semantics Possible,” Mind, Language and Reality, Philosophical Papers, Vol. 2, Cambridge University Press.
, 1934a, “Review of the Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. Vol. 4. The Simplest Mathematics,” Isis
22, 551–553.Google Scholar
, 1947, “The Problem of Interpreting Modal Logic,” The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 12, 43–48.
1953a, “Reference and Modality,” From a Logical Point of View, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, second edition 1961, 139–159 (references are to the second edition.).
1953b, “Three Grades of Modal Involvement,” The Ways of Paradox, Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1976, 158–176.
1953c, “Two Dogmas of Empiricism,” From a Logical Point of View, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, second edition 1961, 20–46 (references are to the second edition.).
1960, Word and Object, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
1969, “Reply to Sellars,” in Words and Objections, ed. and , Dordrecht: Reidel, 1969, 337–340.
1970, Philosophy of Logic, Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
,
1978, “Necessity and Fate in Stoic Philosophy” in The Stoics, ed. , University of California Press. 187–202.
2002, Peirce's Scientific Metaphysics, Nashville: Vanderbilt University Press.
, 1989, Aspects of Aristotle's Logic of Modalities, Dordrecht: Kluwer.
, 2011, Aristotle's Modal Proofs: Prior Analytics A8-22 in Predicate Logic, The New Synthese Historical Library 68, Dordrecht: Springer.
2013, “The Birth of Proof: Modality and Deductive Reasoning,” Logic and Its Applications, ed. , Springer Lecture Notes in Computer Science LNCS 7750, Springer: Berlin, 34–49.
1969, “Fate and Necessity,” in Stoic Philosophy, ed. , Cambridge University Press. 112–132.
, 1978, “Necessity and Fate in Stoic Philosophy,” in The Stoics, ed. , University of California Press.
1973, The Existential Graphs of Charles S. Peirce, The Hague: Mouton.
, 2012, “A Method of Modal Proof in Aristotle,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy
42, 179–261.Google Scholar
, and , 1949, Aristotle's Prior and Posterior Analytics: A Revised Text with Introduction and Commentary, Oxford: Clarendon Press. Reprinted with corrections 1957, 1965. Page references to the 1957 printing.
, ,
1918, “The Philosophy of Logical Atomism,” in Logic and Knowledge, Ed , New York: Capricorn Books, 1955, 177–281.
, 1937. A Critical Exposition of the Philosophy of Leibniz. 2nd ed., London: Allen & Unwin.
1976, The Problems of Philosophy, Oxford University Press [1st edition 1912].
2005, The Stoics on Determinism and Compatibilism, Ashgate.
, 1959, Physics of the Stoics. Princeton University Press.
, 1983, “On Finding Compactness in Aristotle,”
History and Philosophy of Logic
4(1 and 2), 1–8.Google Scholar
, Kant's Conception of Cognition,” In , and
The Sensible and Intelligible Worlds: New Essays on Kant's Metaphysics and Epistemology, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
, (forthcoming). “ ,
1977, “Diodorus Cronus and Hellenistic Philosophy,”
Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society
203, 74–120.Google Scholar
, 1982, ‘The Stoic Criterion of Identity’, Phronesis, 27, 255–75.
1982, Die Aristotelische Modaltheorie, Berlin and New York: de Gruyter.
, 2006, “Proof and persuasion,” in The Cambridge History of History of Science. Vol. III. Early Modern Science, eds and , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 132–175.
, Sextus Empiricus, 1939–1949, Sextus Empiricus, ed. , Cambridge, MA: Loeb.
1983, Alexander of Aphrodisias on Fate, London: Duckworth.
, 1973, The propositional logic of Avicenna, Dordrecht: Riedel.
, 2002, The Iconic Logic of Peirce's Graphs, Cambridge MA: MIT Press.
, 2013, “Peirce's Deductive Logic,” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/peirce-logic/ (downloaded September 10, 2014).
, and , 2001, Four Dimensionalism: A Study in Persistence and Ontology, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
, 1990. Leibniz and Arnauld: A Commentary on Their Correspondence, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
, 1989, Aristotle: Prior Analytics, Indianapolis and Cambridge: Hackett.
,
1980a, “Causation, Laws, and Necessity” in Doubt and Dogmatism, ed. , , . Oxford: Clarendon Press.
, 1980b, Necessity, Cause, and Blame: Perspectives on Aristotle's Theory, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
1988, Matter, Space and Motion, Ithaca NY: Cornell University Press.
,
,
2012, “Kant on Complete Determination and Infinite Judgment,”
British Journal of the History of Philosophy
20(6), 1117–1139.Google Scholar
2016, Kant's Modal Metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Kant's Transcendental Idealism,” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
(forthcoming) “ ,
1805, A Short Statement…, Edinburgh: , and & Co.
, 2007. Diagrammatology: An Investigation on the Borderlines of Phenomenology, Ontology and Semiotics, Dordrecht: Springer.
1978, “Stoic Determinism and Moral Responsibility,” The Stoics, ed. , University of California Press, 1978, 203–232.
, 2002, “An Outline of Avicenna's Syllogistic,” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie
84, 129–160.Google Scholar
, 2004, “Arabic Logic,” in Handbook of the History of Logic. Vol.1. Greek, Indian and Arabic Logic, ed. and , Elsevier, 523–596.
2010, “Appendix: Readings of the Subject Term,” Arabic Sciences and Philosophy
20, 119–124.Google Scholar
2013a, “Arabic and Islamic Philosophy of Language and Logic,” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2013 Edition), ed. Edward N. Zalta, http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2013/entries/arabic-islamic-language/
2013b, “Avicenna on the Syllogism,” in Interpreting Avicenna: Critical Essays, ed. , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 48–70.
2014, “Afḍal al-Dīn al-Khūnajī (d. 1248) on the Conversion of Modal Propositions,” Oriens
42, 454–513.Google Scholar
1987, “Origins of the Concept of Natural Law,” Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy
2, 79–94.Google Scholar
, 1994, “Assertoric vs. Modal Syllogistic,”
Ancient Philosophy
14, special issue, 39–51.Google Scholar
2009, Aristotle's Prior Analytics, Book 1, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
,
2013, Locke's Metaphysics, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
1991, “The Two Barbaras,” History and Philosophy of Logic 12, 135–149.
, 1996. The Logic of Essentialism. An Interpretation of Aristotle's Modal Syllogistic, Dordrecht:
Boston and London: Kluwer.
2001, Mediaeval Modal Systems, Aldershot: Ashgate.
2008, “Logic and Metaphysics in Avicenna's Modal Syllogistic,” in The Unity of Science in the Arabic Tradition: science, Logic, Epistemology and Their Interactions, ed. , and , Dordrecht: Kluwer-Springer, 283–295.
2010, “Abharī on the Logic of Conjunctive Terms,” Arabic Sciences and Philosophy
20, 105–117.Google Scholar
2012, “Syllogisms about Possibility and Necessity in Avicenna and Tusi,” in Insolubles and Consequences, ed. and , London: College Publications, 239–248.
1946, Summa contra gentiles, Romae: Apud sedem commissionis Leoninae.
, 1949, Quaestiones Disputatae de Anima, translated by, , St. Louis and London: B. Herder Book Co.
1952a, 1953, 1954, Questiones Disputatae de Veritate, Questions 1–9 translated by , Questions 10–20 translated by , Questions 21–29 translated by , Chicago, Henry Regnery.
1952b, Quaestiones Disputatae de Potentia Dei, translated by the
Westminster, MD: Newman Press, 1952, reprint of 1932.
1962, Expositio libri Peryermeneias, Commentary by finished by , translated by , Milwaukee: Marquette University Press.
1964–1981, Summa theologiae. Latin text and English translation, introductions, notes, appendices, and glossaries, London: Blackfriars in conjunction with Eyre and Spottiswoode.
1993, “Modal Logics for Conceptual Graphs, in Proceedings of First International Conference on Conceptual Structures, Vol. 699 of LNCS, Berlin: Springer-Verlag.
( ,
1844, Aristotelis organon graece I, Leipzig: Hahn.
, 1992, Galileo's Logic of Discovery and Proof, Dordrecht: Kluwer.
, 2014, “Connexive Logic,” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2014 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/logic-connexive/
, 1998, “Kant on the Material Grounds of Possibility,” Review of Metaphysics
52, 369–395.Google Scholar
, and , 1726, Logick, London: John Clark.
, 2002, Aristoteles: Peri Hermeneias, 2nd ed., Berlin: Akademie Verlag.
, 2012, “
De interpretatione
,” in The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle, ed. , Oxford: Oxford University Press, 81–112.
1996, Aristotle's De Interpretatione: Contradiction and Dialectic, Oxford, Clarendon Press.
, 2013, Modal Logic as Matphysica, Oxford University Press.
, 1922, Tractatus Logic-Philosophicus. (Translated by ), London: Kegan Paul.
, 2003, Selected Essays on Scotus and Ockham, Franciscan Institute Publications.
, 1984, “Kant's Compatibilism,” in Self and Nature in Kant's Philosophy, ed. , Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
, 2014, “God, Totality and Possibility in Kant's Only Possible Argument
,” Kantian Review, 19(1), 27–51.Google Scholar
, 1986, “Peirce's Philosophy of Logic,” Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society
22, 1–22.Google Scholar
, 1997a, “Peirce and Philo,” Studies in the Logic of Charles Sanders Peirce, ed. , , and , Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 402–417.
1997b, “Peirce's Graphs,” in Conceptual Structures: Fulfilling Peirce's Dream, ed. , et al., Berlin: Springer.
1997c, “The Tinctures and Implicit Quantification over Worlds, in The Rule of Reason, ed. and , Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 96–119.