Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-j824f Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-17T19:55:51.572Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bibliography

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  11 May 2018

Matthew D. Walker
Affiliation:
Yale-NUS College
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2018

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Primary Sources

Allan, D. J., ed. 1936. Aristotelis: De Caelo. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Balme, D. M., trans. and comm. [1972] 1999. Aristotle: De Partibus Animalium I and De Generatione Animalium I. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Balme, D. M., ed. 2002. Aristotle: Historia Animalium Volume I: Books I–X. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Barnes, J., ed. 1984. The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation, 2 vols. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Bywater, I., ed. 1894. Aristotelis: Ethica Nicomachea. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chroust, A.-H., trans. and comm. 1964. Aristotle: Protrepticus – A Reconstruction. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Drossaart Lulofs, H. J., ed. 1965. Aristotelis: De Generatione Animalium. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Düring, I., ed. and comm. 1961. Aristotle’s Protrepticus: An Attempt at Reconstruction. Gothenburg: Studia Graeca et Latina Gothoburgensia.Google Scholar
Fritz, K. von and Kapp, E., ed. and trans. 1950. Aristotle’s Constitution of Athens and Related Texts. New York: Hafner.Google Scholar
Furth, M., trans. 1985. Aristotle: Metaphysics, Books Zeta, Eta, Theta, Iota (VII–X). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.Google Scholar
Hamlyn, D. W., trans. and comm. [1968] 1993. Aristotle: De Anima: Books II and III. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hett, W. S., ed. and trans. Aristotle: On the Soul, Parva Naturalia, On Breath. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Hicks, R. D., ed. and comm. 1907. Aristotle: De Anima. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Irwin, T. H., trans. and comm. 1999. Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics, 2nd edn. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.Google Scholar
Joachim, H. H., ed. and comm. 1926. Aristotle: On Coming-to-Be and Passing-Away. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Lennox, J. G., trans. and comm. 2001a. Aristotle: On the Parts of Animals. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Louis, P., ed. and trans. 1956. Aristote: Les parties des animaux. Paris: Les Belles Lettres.Google Scholar
Louis, P. 1973, ed. and trans. Aristote: Marche des animaux; Mouvement des animaux; Index des traités biologiques. Paris: Les Belles Lettres.Google Scholar
Louis, P. 1982, ed. and trans. Aristote: Météorologiques, 2 vols. Paris: Les Belles Lettres.Google Scholar
Louis, P. 1994, ed. and trans. Aristote: Problemes, 3 vols. Paris: Les Belles Lettres.Google Scholar
Mayhew, R., ed. and trans. 2011. Aristotle: Problems, 2 vols. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. C., ed. and comm. 1978. Aristotle’s De Motu Animalium. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Pakaluk, M., trans. and comm. 1999. Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics, Books VIII and IX. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Peck, A. L. and Forster, E. S., ed. and trans. 1937. Aristotle: Parts of Animals, Movement of Animals, Progression of Animals. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rackham, H., ed. and trans. 1926. Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rackham, H., ed. and trans. 1932. Aristotle: Politics. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rackham, H., ed. and trans. 1935. Aristotle: Athenian Constitution, Eudemian Ethics, Virtues and Vices. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Reeve, C. D. C., trans. and comm. 2013. Aristotle on Practical Wisdom: Nicomachean Ethics VI. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reeve, C. D. C, trans. and comm. 2014. Nicomachean Ethics. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D., ed. and comm. 1924. Aristotle’s Metaphysics, 2 vols. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D., ed. 1950. Aristotelis: Physica. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D., ed. and comm. 1955. Aristotle: Parva Naturalia. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ross, W. D., ed. 1956. Aristotelis: De Anima. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D., ed. 1957. Aristotelis: Politica. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D., ed. 1958. Aristotelis: Topica et Sophistici Elenchi. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ross, W. D., ed. 1959. Aristotelis: Ars Rhetorica. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D., ed. 1964. Aristotelis: Analytica Priora et Posteriora. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sachs, J., trans. 2001. Aristotle’s De Anima and On Memory and Recollection. Santa Fe: Green Lion Press.Google Scholar
Sachs, J., trans. 2002. Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics. Newburyport: Focus.Google Scholar
Shields, C., trans. and comm. 2016. Aristotle: De Anima. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Simpson, P. L. P., trans. and comm. 2013a. The Eudemian Ethics of Aristotle. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers.Google Scholar
Simpson, P. L. P., trans. and comm. 2014. The Great Ethics of Aristotle. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers.Google Scholar
Susemihl, F., ed. 1883. Aristotelis: Magna Moralia. Leipzig: Teubner.Google Scholar
Taylor, C. C. W., trans. and comm. 2006. Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics, Books II–IV. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Tredennick, H., ed. and trans. 1933. Aristotle: Metaphysics: I–IX. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Tredennick, H., and Armstrong, G. C., ed. and trans. 1935. Aristotle: Metaphysics, X–XIV, Oeconomica, Magna Moralia. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Tredennick, H., and Forster, E. S., ed. and trans. 1960. Aristotle: Posterior Analytics and Topica. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Walzer, R. R. and Mingay, J. M., ed. 1991. Aristotelis: Ethica Eudemia. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Woods, M., trans. and comm. 1992. Aristotle: Eudemian Ethics, Books I, II, VIII, 2nd edn. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Bloom, A., trans. [1968] 1991. The Republic of Plato. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Burnet, J., ed. 1900–1907. Platonis: Opera, 5 vols. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M., ed. 1997. Plato: Collected Works. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.Google Scholar
Denyer, N., ed. and comm. 2001. Plato: Alcibiades. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lamb, W. R. M., ed. and trans. 1925. Plato: Lysis, Symposium, Gorgias. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Lamb, W. R. M., ed. and trans. 1927. Plato: Charmides, Alcibiades, Hipparchus, Lovers, Theages, Minos, Epinomis. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Lord, C. trans. 1987. “Alcibiades I.” In The Roots of Political Philosophy: Ten Forgotten Socratic Dialogues, ed. Pangle, T. L., 175221. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Rowe, C. J., ed. and trans. 1998. Plato: Symposium. Warminster: Aris & Phillips.Google Scholar
Alfarabi. [1962] 2001. Philosophy of Plato and Aristotle, trans. Mahdi, M.. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Alfarabi. 2001. The Harmonization of the Opinions of the Two Sages, Plato the Divine and Aristotle. In Alfarabi: The Political Writings, trans. Butterworth, C. E., 115168. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Aquinas, T. [1951] 1994. Commentary on Aristotle’s De Anima, trans. Foster, K. and Humphries, S.. Notre Dame: Dumb Ox Books.Google Scholar
Aquinas, T. [1964] 2003. Commentary on Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, trans. Litzinger, C.J.. Notre Dame: Dumb Ox Books.Google Scholar
Aquinas, T. [1920] 2006. The Summa Theologica of St. Thomas Aquinas, trans. The Fathers of the English Dominican Province. URL: http://www.newadvent.org/summa/.Google Scholar
Caston, V., trans. and comm. 2012. Alexander of Aphrodisias: On the Soul, Part I, Soul as Form of the Body, Parts of the Soul, Nourishment, and Perception. London: Bristol Classical Press.Google Scholar
des Places, É., ed. and trans. 1989. Jamblique: Protreptique. Paris: Les Belles Lettres.Google Scholar
Diels, H. and Kranz, W., ed. 1951. Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker. Berlin: Weidmann.Google Scholar
Dooley, W. E., trans. and comm. 1989. Alexander of Aphrodisias: On Aristotle’s Metaphysics 1. London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
Einarson, B. and Link, G. K. K., ed. and trans. Theophrastus: De Causis Plantarum I. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Fackenheim, E. L. 1945. “A Treatise on Love by Ibn Sina” (with translation). Mediaeval Studies 7: 208228.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Festa, N., ed. 1891. Iamblichi De Communi Mathematica Scientia. Leipzig: Teubner.Google Scholar
Griffin, M., trans. and comm. 2015. Olympiodorus: Life of Plato and On Plato First Alcibiades 1–9. London: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
Hicks, R. D., ed. and trans. 1925. Diogenes Laertius: Lives of the Eminent Philosophers I–II. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Jones, W. H. S., ed. and trans. 1931. Hippocrates, vol. 4. London: William Heinemann.Google Scholar
Marchant, E. C., ed. and trans. 1938. Xenophon: Memorabilia, Oeconomicus, Symposium, Apology. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Norlin, G., ed. and trans. 1929. Isocrates, 2 vols. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
O’Neill, W., trans. and comm. 1971. Proclus: Alcibiades I: A Translation and Commentary, 2nd ed. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Perrin, B., ed. and trans. 1916. Plutarch’s Lives: vol. iv. London: William Heinemann.Google Scholar
Pistelli, H. G. 1888. Iamblichi Protrepticus. Leipzig: Teubner.Google Scholar
Relihan, J. C., trans. and comm. 2001. Boethius: Consolation of Philosophy. Indianapolis and Cambridge: Hackett Publishing.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D. and Fobes, F. H., ed. and trans. 1967. Theophrastus: Metaphysics. Hildesheim: Georg Olms Verlagsbuchhandlung.Google Scholar
Todd, R. B., trans. and comm. 1996. Themistius: On Aristotle on the Soul. London: Bristol Classical Press.Google Scholar
Van Hook, L., ed. and trans. 1945. Isocrates III. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Achtenberg, D. [1988] 1995. “Human Being, Beast and God: The Place of Human Happiness According to Aristotle and Some Twentieth-Century Philosophers.” In The Crossroads of Norm and Nature: Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics and Metaphysics, ed. Sim, M., 2950. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield. (Originally in The St. John’s Review 38.)Google Scholar
Achtenberg, D. 2002. Cognition of Value in Aristotle’s Ethics: Promise of Enrichment, Threat of Destruction. Albany: State University of New York Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ackrill, J. L. [1974] 1980. “Aristotle on Eudaimonia.” In Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics, ed. Rorty, A. O., 1533. Berkeley: University of California Press. (Originally in Proceedings of the British Academy 60.)Google Scholar
Allan, D. J. 1975. “A Passage from Iamblichus in Praise of the Contemplative Life.” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 57: 246268.Google Scholar
Annas, J. 1981. An Introduction to Plato’s Republic. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Annas, J. 1985. “Self-Knowledge in Early Plato.” In Platonic Investigations, ed. O’Meara, D., 111138. Washington, D.C.: Catholic University of America Press.Google Scholar
Annas, J. 1993. The Morality of Happiness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Annas, J. 1999. Platonic Ethics, Old and New. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Anscombe, G. E. M. 1953. “The Principle of Individuation.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 27 supp.: 8395.Google Scholar
Armstrong, J. M. 2004. “After the Ascent: Plato on Becoming Like God.Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 26: 171183.Google Scholar
Arnhart, L. 1998. Darwinian Natural Right: The Biological Ethics of Human Nature. Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Aubenque, P. 1963. Le prudence chez Aristote. Presses Universitaires de France.Google Scholar
Baehr, J. 2012. “Two Types of Wisdom.Acta Analytica 27: 8197.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baehr, J. 2014. “Sophia.” In Virtues and Their Vices, ed. Timpe, K. and Boyd, C., 303323. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Balme, D. M. 1987. “Teleology and Necessity.” In Philosophical Issues in Aristotle’s Biology, ed. Gotthelf, A. and Lennox, J. G., 275285. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Balot, R. K. 2014. Courage in the Democratic Polis: Ideology and Critique in Classical Athens. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Barnes, J. 1995. “Life and Work.” In The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle, 126. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Barnes, J. [1997] 2015. “Roman Aristotle.” In Mantissa: Essays in Ancient Philosophy IV, ed. Bonelli, M., 408478. Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Originally in Philosophia Togata II, ed. J. Barnes and M. Griffin.)Google Scholar
Baynham, E. J. and Tarrant, H.. 2012. “Fourth-Century Politics and the Date of the Alcibiades I.” In Alcibiades and the Socratic Lover-Educator, ed. Johnson, M. and Tarrant, H., 215222. London: Bristol Classical Press.Google Scholar
Beere, J. 2009. Doing and Being: An Interpretation of Aristotle’s Metaphysics Theta. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bluck, R. S. 1953. “The Origin of the Greater Alcibiades.Classical Quarterly 47: 4652.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bobonich, C. 2007. “Why Should Philosophers Rule: Plato’s Republic and Aristotle’s Protrepticus.Social Philosophy & Policy 24: 153175.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bodéüs, R. 2000. Aristotle and the Theology of the Living Immortals, trans. Garrett, J.. Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Bodnar, I. 2015. “The Problemata Physica: An Introduction.” In The Aristotelian Problemata Physica, ed. Mayhew, R., 19. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
Bostock, D. 2000. Aristotle’s Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Brague, R. 1988. Aristote et le question du monde: Essai sur le contexte cosmologique et anthropologique de l’ontologie. Presses Universitaires de France.Google Scholar
Brink, D. O. 1999. “Eudaimonism, Love and Friendship, and Political Community.” In Human Flourishing, ed. Paul, E. F., Miller, F. D. Jr., and Paul, J., 252289. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broadie, S. 1991. Ethics with Aristotle. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Broadie, S. 1999. “Aristotle’s Elusive Summum Bonum.” In Human Flourishing, ed. Paul, E. F., Miller, F., and Paul, J., 233251. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, E. 2000. “Justice and Compulsion for Plato’s Philosopher-Rulers.Ancient Philosophy 20: 117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, E. 2004. “Minding the Gap in Plato’s Republic.Philosophical Studies 117: 275302.Google Scholar
Brown, E. 2006. “Wishing for Fortune, Choosing Activity: Aristotle on External Goods and Happiness.Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 22: 221256.Google Scholar
Brown, E. 2012. “The Unity of the Soul in Plato’s Republic.” In Plato and the Divided Self, ed. Barney, R., Brennan, T., and Brittain, C., 5373. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, L. 1997. “What Is the ‘Mean Relative to Us’ in Aristotle’s Ethics?Phronesis 42: 7793.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burnyeat, M. F. 1980. “Aristotle on Learning to Be Good.” In Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics, ed. Rorty, A. O., 6992. Berkeley: University of California Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burnyeat, M. F. 2008. Aristotle’s Divine Intellect: The Aquinas Lecture, 28. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press.Google Scholar
Bush, S. S. 2008. “Divine and Human Happiness in Nicomachean Ethics.Philosophical Review 117: 4975.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bywater, I. 1869. “On a Lost Dialogue of Aristotle.Journal of Philology 2: 5569.Google Scholar
Cambiano, G. 2012. “The Desire to Know: Metaphysics A 1.In Aristotle’s Metaphysics A: Symposium Aristotelicum, ed. Steele, C. and Primavesi, O., 142. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Case, T. (1910) 1996. “Aristotle.” In Aristotle’s Philosophical Development: Problems and Prospects, ed. Wians, W. O., 140. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield. (Originally in Encyclopedia Brittanica.)Google Scholar
Casebeer, W. D. 2003. Natural Ethical Facts: Evolution, Connectionism, and Moral Cognition. Cambridge and London: The MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caston, V. 1996. “Aristotle on the Relation of the Intellect to the Body: Commentary on Broadie.Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 12: 170192.Google Scholar
Caston, V. 1999. “Aristotle’s Two Intellects: A Modest Proposal.Phronesis 44: 199227.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caston, V. 2006. “Aristotle’s Psychology.” In A Companion to Ancient Philosophy, ed. Gill, M. L. and Pellegrin, P., 316346. Malden: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Caston, V. 2009. “Phantasia and Thought.” In A Companion to Aristotle, ed. Anagastopolos, G., 322334. Malden: Wiley-Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cates, D. F. 2009. Aquinas on the Emotions: A Religious-Ethical Inquiry. Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press.Google Scholar
Charles, D. 1999. “Aristotle on Well-Being and Intellectual Contemplation.Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 73 supp.: 205223.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Charlton, W. 1987. “Aristotle on the Place of Mind in Nature.In Philosophical Issues in Aristotle’s Biology, ed. Gotthelf, A. and Lennox, J. G., 408423. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chroust, A.-H. 1973. Aristotle: New Light on His Life and on Some of His Lost Works, vol. 1. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Clark, S. R. L. 1975. Aristotle’s Man: Speculations on Aristotelian Anthropology. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Code, A. 1984. “The Aporematic Approach to Primary Being in Metaphysics Z.Canadian Journal of Philosophy 14 supp.: 120.Google Scholar
Cohoe, C. 2014. “Nous in Aristotle’s De Anima.Philosophy Compass 9: 594604.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Collins, J. H. II. 2015. Exhortations to Philosophy: The Protreptics of Plato, Isocrates, and Aristotle. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Conway, D. 2000. The Rediscovery of Wisdom: From Here to Antiquity in Quest of Sophia. Houndmills and London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. [1973] 1999. “The Magna Moralia and Aristotle’s Moral Philosophy.” In Reason and Emotion, 195211. Princeton: Princeton University Press. (Originally in American Journal of Philology 94.)Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. [1975] 1986. Reason and the Human Good in Aristotle. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing. (Originally Harvard University Press.)Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. [1977] 1999. “Friendship and the Good in Aristotle.” In Reason and Emotion, 336355. Princeton: Princeton University Press. (Originally in Philosophical Review 86.)Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. [1985] 1999. “Aristotle on the Goods of Fortune.” In Reason and Emotion, 292311. Princeton: Princeton University Press. (Originally in Philosophical Review 94.)Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. [1987] 1999. “Contemplation and Happiness: A Reconsideration.” In Reason and Emotion, 212236. Princeton: Princeton University Press. (Originally in Synthese 72.)Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. [1988] 1999. “Some Remarks on Aristotle’s Moral Psychology.” In Reason and Emotion, 237252. Princeton: Princeton University Press. (Originally in Southern Journal of Philosophy 27 supplement.)Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. 1996. “An Aristotelian Theory of the Emotions.” In Essays on Aristotle’s Rhetoric, ed. Rorty, A. O., 238257. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. [1996] 1999. “Reason, Moral Virtue, and Moral Value.” In Reason and Emotion, 253280. Princeton: Princeton University Press. (Originally in Rationality in Greek Thought, ed. M. Frede and G. Striker.)Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. [2003] 2004. “Plato and Aristotle on ‘Finality’ and ‘(Self-)Sufficiency.” In Knowledge, Nature, and the Good: Essays in Ancient Philosophy, 270308. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. 2004. “Plato, Isocrates, and Cicero on the Independence of Oratory from Philosophy.” In Knowledge, Nature, and the Good: Essays in Ancient Philosophy, 6580. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. 2009. “Nicomachean Ethics VII.1–2: Introduction, Method, Puzzles.” In Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics, Book VII Symposium Aristotelicum, ed. Natali, C., 939. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. 2010. “Political Community and the Highest Good.” In Being, Nature, and Life in Aristotle: Essays in Honor of Allan Gotthelf, ed. Lennox, J. G. and Bolton, R., 212264. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Corcilius, K. 2011. “Aristotle’s Definition of Non-Rational Pleasure and Pain and Desire.” In Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics: A Critical Guide, ed. Miller, J., 117143. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Corcilius, K. and Gregoric, P.. 2010. “Separability vs. Difference: Parts and Capacities of the Soul in Aristotle.Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 39: 81120.Google Scholar
Courcelle, P. 1974. Connais-toi toi-meme de Socrate a Saint Bernard, vol. I. Paris: Etudes Augustiniennes.Google Scholar
Curzer, H. J. 1991. “Aristotle’s Much Maligned Megalopsychos.Australasian Journal of Philosophy 69: 131151.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Curzer, H. J. 2012. Aristotle & the Virtues. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dahl, N. 2011. “Contemplation and Eudaimonia in the Nicomachean Ethics.” In Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics: A Critical Guide, ed. Miller, J., 6691. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Defourny, P. 1978. “Contemplation in Aristotle’s Ethics.” In Articles on Aristotle. vol. 2, Ethics and Politics, ed. Barnes, J., Schofield, M., and Sorabji, R., 104112. New York: St. Martin’s Press.Google Scholar
De Haas, F. 2009. “Know Thyself: Plato and Aristotle on Awareness.” In Ancient Perspectives on Aristotle’s De Anima, ed. Van Riel, G. and Destreé, P., 4969. Leuven: Leuven University Press.Google Scholar
Den Uyl, D. 1991. The Virtue of Prudence. New York: Peter Lang.Google Scholar
Depew, D. J. 1981. “Aristotle’s De Anima and Marx’s Theory of Man.Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal 8: 133185.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Depew, D. J. 1995. “Humans and Other Political Animals in Aristotle’s History of Animals.Phronesis 40: 156181.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Depew, D. J. 2004. “The Inscription of Isocrates into Aristotle’s Practical Philosophy.” In Isocrates and Civic Education, ed. Poulakos, T. and Depew, D., 157185. Austin: University of Texas Press.Google Scholar
Detienne, M. 1982. “Between Beasts and Gods.” In Myth, Religion, and Society, ed. Gordon, R. L., 215228. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Diamond, E. 2014. “Aristotle’s Appropriation of Plato’s Sun Analogy in De Anima.Apeiron 47: 356389.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Diamond, E. 2015. Mortal Imitations of Divine Life: The Nature of the Soul in Aristotle’s De Anima. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
Elders, L. 1972. Aristotle’s Theology: A Commentary on Book Λ of the Metaphysics. Assen: Van Gorcum.Google Scholar
Everson, S. 1998. “Aristotle on Nature and Value.” In Ethics: Companions to Ancient Thought 4, ed. Everson, S., 77106. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feser, E. 2013. “The New Atheists and the Cosmological Argument.Midwest Studies in Philosophy 37: 154177.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foot, P. [2001] 2003. Natural Goodness. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Fossheim, H. 2011. “Justice in the Nicomachean Ethics Book V.” In Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics: A Critical Guide, ed. Miller, J., 254275. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Foucault, M. [2001] 2005. The Hermeneutics of the Subject: Lectures at the College de France, 1981–1982. Ed. Gros, F. and trans. Burchell, G.. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Frankena, W. K. 1939. “The Naturalistic Fallacy.Mind 48: 464477.Google Scholar
Frankfurt, H. [1992] 1999. “The Usefulness of Final Ends.” In Necessity, Volition, and Love, 8294. New York: Cambridge University Press. (Originally in Iyyun 41.)Google Scholar
Frede, D. 2014. “A Swarm of Virtues: On the Unity and Completeness of Aristotle’s Scheme of Character-Virtues.” In Strategies of Argument: Essays in Ancient Ethics, Epistemology, and Logic, ed. Lee, M., 83103. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Frede, M. 1992. “On Aristotle’s Conception of Soul.” In Essays on Aristotle’s De Anima, ed. Nussbaum, M. C. and Rorty, A. O., 93107. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Frede, M. 2008. “Aristotle’s Account of the Origins of Philosophy.” In The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy, ed. Curd, P. and Graham, D. W., 501529. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Freeland, C. A. 1987. “Aristotle on Bodies, Matter, and Potentiality.” In Philosophical Issues in Aristotle’s Biology, ed. Gotthelf, A. and Lennox, J. G., 392407. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Freeland, C. A. 1994. “Aristotle on Perception, Appetition, and Self-Motion.” In Self-Movers, ed. Gill, M. L. and Lennox, J. G., 3563. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Freudenthal, G. 1995. Aristotle’s Theory of Material Substance: Heat and Pneuma, Form and Soul. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Friedländer, P. 1964. Plato, vol. 2, trans. Meyerhoff, H.. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Furth, M. 1988. Substance, Form, and Psyche: An Aristotelean Metaphysics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gadamer, H.-G. 1928. “Der Aristotelische Protreptikos und die Entwicklungsgeschichtliche Betrachtung der Aristotelischen Ethik.Hermes 63: 138164.Google Scholar
Gadamer, H.-G. 1986. The Idea of the Good in Platonic-Aristotelian Philosophy. Trans. Smith, P. C.. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Garver, E. 2006. Confronting Aristotle’s Ethics: Ancient and Modern Morality. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Gauthier, R. A. and Jolif, J. Y., 2002. L’Éthique à Nicomaque, 2nd edn. Louvain-la-Neuve: Éditions Peeters.Google Scholar
Gentzler, J. 2004. “The Attractions and Delights of Goodness.Philosophical Quarterly 54: 353367.Google Scholar
Gerson, L. P. 2005. Aristotle and Other Platonists. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Gill, C. 2006. The Structured Self in Hellenistic and Roman Thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gill, M. L. 1989a. “Aristotle on Matters of Life and Death.Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium on Ancient Philosophy 5: 187205.Google Scholar
Gill, M. L. 1989b. Aristotle on Substance: The Paradox of Unity. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Gotthelf, A. 1975. “Aristotle’s Conception of Final Causality.” Ph.D. dissertation, Columbia University.Google Scholar
Gotthelf, A. [1985] 2012. “Notes Toward a Study of Substance and Essence in Aristotle’s Parts of Animals II-IV.” In Teleology, First Principles, and Scientific Method in Aristotle’s Biology, 217240. Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Originally in Aristotle on Nature and Living Things.)Google Scholar
Gotthelf, A. [1987] 2012. “Aristotle’s Conception of Final Causality.” In Teleology, First Principles, and Scientific Method in Aristotle’s Biology, 344. Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Originally in Philosophical Issues in Aristotle’s Biology.)Google Scholar
Gotthelf, A. [1988] 2012. “The Place of the Good in Aristotle’s Natural Teleology.” In Teleology, First Principles, and Scientific Method in Aristotle’s Biology, 344. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 4566. (Originally in Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium on Ancient Philosophy 4.)Google Scholar
Gottlieb, P. 2009. The Virtue of Aristotle’s Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Gottlieb, P. and Sober, E.. Forthcoming. “Aristotle on ‘Nature Does Nothing in Vain.’” History of Philosophy of Science.Google Scholar
Greenwood, L. H. G., ed., trans., and comm. 1909. Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics Book VI. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Grene, M. 1963. A Portrait of Aristotle. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Grönroos, G. 2007. “Listening to Reason in Aristotle’s Moral Psychology.Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 32: 251271.Google Scholar
Hackforth, R. 1950. “Immortality in Plato’s Symposium.The Classical Review 64: 4345.Google Scholar
Halper, E. 1993. “The Rational Basis of Aristotle’s Virtue.” In Form and Reason: Essays in Metaphysics, 5773. Albany: State University of Albany Press.Google Scholar
Halper, E. 1995. “The Substance of Aristotle’s Ethics.” In The Crossroads of Norm and Nature: Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics and Metaphysics, ed. Sim, M., 328. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Hardie, W. F. R. 1965. “The Final Good in Aristotle’s Ethics.Philosophy 40: 277295.Google Scholar
Hardie, W. F. R. 1979. “Aristotle on the Best Life for a Man.Philosophy 54: 3550.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hare, J. E. 2007. God and Morality: A Philosophical History. Malden: Blackwell Publishing.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hegel, G. W. F. 1894. Lectures on the History of Philosophy, vol. II, trans. Haldane, E. S. and Simson, F. H.. London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trübner.Google Scholar
Heinaman, R. 2000. “Cooper on Ancient Ethics.Polis 17: 161185.Google Scholar
Henry, D. 2013. “Optimality and Teleology in Aristotle’s Natural Science.Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 45: 225263.Google Scholar
Henry, D. and Nielsen, K. M.. 2015. “Introduction.” In Bridging the Gap between Aristotle’s Science and Ethics, 125. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horster, M. 2010. “Religious Landscape and Sacred Ground: Relationships between Space and Cult in the Greek World.Revue de l’histoire des religions 4: 435458.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hughes, G. J. 2001. Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Aristotle on Ethics. London and New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Hursthouse, R. 1999. On Virtue Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hutchinson, D. S., 1988. “Review of Aristotle: The Power of Perception by Deborah Modrak.Phoenix 42: 7677.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hutchinson, D. S. and Johnson, M. R.. 2005. “Authenticating Aristotle’s Protrepticus.Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 29: 193294.Google Scholar
Hutchinson, D. S. and Johnson, M. R.. 2014. “Protreptic Aspects of the Nicomachean Ethics.” In The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, ed. Polansky, R., 383409. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hutchinson, D. S. and Johnson, M. R.. Unpublished work A. Aristotle: Protrepticus, with Commentary. www.protrepticus.info.Google Scholar
Hutchinson, D. S. and Johnson, M. R.Unpublished work B. “The Antidosis of Isocrates and Aristotle’s Protrepticus.” www.protrepticus.info.Google Scholar
Inglis, K. 2014. “Philosophical Virtue: In Defense of the Grand End.” In The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, ed. Polansky, R., 263287. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Irwin, T. H. 1980. “The Metaphysical and Psychological Basis of Aristotle’s Ethics.” In Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics, ed. Rorty, A. O., 3553. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Inglis, K. 1988. Aristotle’s First Principles. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Inglis, K. 1991. “The Structure of Aristotelian Happiness.Ethics 101: 382391.Google Scholar
Inglis, K. 1995. Plato’s Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Inglis, K. 2007. The Development of Ethics: A Historical and Critical Study, vol. 1. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Inglis, K. 2009. The Development of Ethics: A Historical and Critical Study, vol. 3. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Inglis, K. 2011. “Beauty and Morality in Aristotle.” In Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics: A Critical Guide, ed. Miller, J., 239253. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Inglis, K. 2012. “Conceptions of Happiness in the Nicomachean Ethics.” In The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle, ed. Shields, C., 495528. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ivanhoe, P. J. and Van Norden, B.. 2005. Readings in Classical Chinese Philosophy, 2nd ed. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.Google Scholar
Jaeger, W. 1957. “Aristotle’s Use of Medicine as Model of Method in His Ethics.” Journal of Hellenic Studies 77–78: 5461.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jaeger, W. 1962. Aristotle: Fundamentals of the History of His Development, 2nd ed., trans. Robinson, R.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Jirsa, J. 2009. “Authenticity of the Alcibiades I: Some Reflections.Listy filologické 132: 225244.Google Scholar
Johansen, T. K. 2012. The Powers of Aristotle’s Soul. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Johnson, D. M. 1999. “God as the True Self: Plato’s Alcibiades I.Ancient Philosophy 19: 119.Google Scholar
Johnson, M. R. 2005. Aristotle on Teleology. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnson, M. R. 2012. “The Medical Background of Aristotle’s Theory of Nature and Spontaneity.Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 27: 105152.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnson, M. R. 2015. “Aristotle’s Architectonic Sciences.” In Theory and Practice in Aristotle’s Natural Science, ed. Ebrey, D., 163186. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnstone, M. A. 2015. “Review of Anna Marmodoro, Aristotle on Perceiving Objects.” Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2015.01.06. http://ndpr.nd.edu/news/54985-aristotle-on-perceiving-objects/.Google Scholar
Jonas, H. [1966] 2001. The Phenomenon of Life: Toward a Philosophical Biology. Evanston: Northwestern University Press. (Originally Harper & Row.)Google Scholar
Kahn, C. H. 1981. “Aristotle and Altruism.Mind 90: 2040.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahn, C. H. 1985. “The Place of the Prime Mover in Aristotle’s Teleology.” In Aristotle on Nature and Living Things: Philosophical and Historical Studies, ed. Gotthelf, A., 183205. Pittsburgh: Mathesis Publications.Google Scholar
Karbowski, J. 2012. “Slaves, Women, and Aristotle’s Natural Teleology.Ancient Philosophy 32: 323353.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kenny, A. 1978. The Aristotelian Ethics: A Study of the Relationship Between the Eudemian and the Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Kenny, A. 1992. Aristotle on the Perfect Life. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keyt, D. [1978] 1983. “Intellectualism in Aristotle.” In Essays in Ancient Greek Philosophy, vol. 2, ed. Anton, J. and Preus, A., 346387. Albany: State University of Albany Press.Google Scholar
King, R. A. H. 2001. Aristotle on Life and Death. London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
Kosman, A. 1969. “Aristotle’s Definition of Motion.Phronesis 14: 4062.Google Scholar
Kosman, A. 1992. “What Does the Maker Mind Make?” In Essays on Aristotle’s De Anima, ed. Nussbaum, M. C. and Rorty, A. O., 343358. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Kosman, A. 2013. The Activity of Being: An Essay on Aristotle’s Ontology. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koziak, B. 2000. Retrieving Political Emotion: Thumos, Aristotle, and Gender. University Park, Pa.: Pennsylvania State University Press.Google Scholar
Kraut, R. 1989. Aristotle on the Human Good. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1989.Google Scholar
Kraut, R. 1993. “In Defense of the Grand End.Ethics 103: 361374.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kraut, R. 2002. Aristotle: Political Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kraut, R. 2013. “An Aesthetic Reading of Aristotle’s Ethics.” In Politeia in Greek and Roman Philosophy, ed. Harte, V. and Lane, M., 231250. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kraut, R. 2016. “Aristotle’s Ethics.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Zalta, E. N., http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/aristotle-ethics/.Google Scholar
Kullmann, W. 1991. “Man as a Political Animal in Aristotle.” In A Companion to Aristotle’s Politics, ed. Keyt, D. and Miller, F. D. Jr., 94117.Google Scholar
Lacrosse, J. 2007. “Some Remarks about a Meeting between Socrates and an Indian (Aristoxenus’ fragment 53).Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 89: 247263.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lachterman, D. R. 1990. “Did Aristotle ‘Develop’?: Reflections on Werner Jaeger’s Thesis.Revue de Philosophie Ancienne 8: 140.Google Scholar
Lai, K. L. 2008. An Introduction to Chinese Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lalonde, G. V. 1991. “Horoi.” In The Athenian Agora (Vol. 19): Inscriptions: Horoi, Poletai Records, and Leases of Public Lands, ed. Lalonde, G. V., Langdon, M. K., and Walbank, M. B., 551. Princeton: The American School of Classical Studies at Athens.Google Scholar
Lawrence, G. 1993. “Aristotle and the Ideal Life.Philosophical Review 102: 134.Google Scholar
Lear, G. R. 2004. Happy Lives and the Highest Good: An Essay on Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Lear, G. R. 2015. “Aristotle on Happiness and Long Life.” In The Quest for the Good Life: Ancient Philosophers on Happiness, ed. Rabbas, O., Emilsson, E. K., Fossheim, H., and Tuominen, M., 127145. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lear, J. 1988. Aristotle: The Desire to Understand. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lear, J. 2000. Happiness, Death, and the Remainder of Life. Cambridge and London: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Leighton, S. R. 1996. “Aristotle and the Emotions.In Essays on Aristotle’s Rhetoric, ed. Rorty, A. O., 206237. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Lennox, J. G. 1985. “Are Aristotelian Species Eternal?” In Aristotle on Nature and Living Things: Philosophical and Historical Studies, ed. Gotthelf, A., 6794. Pittsburgh: Mathesis Publications.Google Scholar
Lennox, J. G. 1999. “The Place of Mankind in Aristotle’s Zoology.Philosophical Topics 27: 116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lennox, J. G. [1999] 2015. “Aristotle on the Biological Roots of Virtue: The Natural History of Natural Virtue.” In Bridging the Gap between Aristotle’s Science and Ethics, ed. Henry, D. and Nielsen, K. M., 193213. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Originally in Biology and the Foundations of Ethics.)Google Scholar
Lennox, J. G. 2001b. “Nature Does Nothing in Vain.” In Aristotle’s Philosophy of Biology, 205223. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lennox, J. G. 2010. “Bios and Explanatory Unity in Aristotle’s Biology.” In Definition in Greek Philosophy, ed. Charles, D., 330356. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Leunissen, M. 2010. Explanation and Teleology in Aristotle’s Science of Nature. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leunissen, M. 2012. “Aristotle on Natural Character and Its Implications for Moral Development.Journal of the History of Philosophy 50: 507530.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leunissen, M. 2015. “Aristotle on Knowing Natural Science for the Sake of Living Well.” In Bridging the Gap between Aristotle’s Science and Ethics, ed. Henry, D. and Nielsen, K. M., 214231. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, F. A. 1995. “Self-Knowledge in Aristotle.Topoi 15: 3958.Google Scholar
Liddell, H. G. and Scott, R.. [1889] 2001. An Intermediate Greek-English Lexicon. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Linck, M. S. 2006. “The Harmony of Plato and Aristotle.Philosophy in the Contemporary World 13: 3844.Google Scholar
Lloyd, G. E. R. 2012. Being, Humanity, and Understanding: Studies in Ancient and Modern Societies. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lockwood, T. 2014. “Competing Ways of Life and Ring Composition (NE x 6–8).” In The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, ed. Polansky, R., 350369. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Long, R. T. 1999. “The Irrelevance of Responsibility.Social Philosophy and Policy 16: 118145.Google Scholar
Lord, C. 1982. Education and Culture in the Political Thought of Aristotle. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Lorenz, H. 2006. The Brute Within: Appetitive Desire in Plato and Aristotle. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
MacIntyre, A. 2006. “Rival Aristotles: Aristotle Against Some Modern Aristotelians.” In Ethics and Politics: Selected Essays, Volume 2, 2240. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Madigan, A. 2001. “Review of Richard Bodéüs, Aristotle and the Theology of the Living Immortals.” Bryn Mawr Classical Review. http://ccat.sas.upenn.edu/bmcr/2001/2001–02-29.html.Google Scholar
Mara, G. M. 1987. “The Role of Philosophy in Aristotle’s Political Science.Polity 19: 375401.Google Scholar
Matthews, G. 1992. “De Anima 2.2–4 and the Meaning of Life.” In Essays on Aristotle’s De Anima, ed. Nussbaum, M. and Rorty, A. O., 185193. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Mayhew, R. 2009. “Rulers and Ruled.” In A Companion to Aristotle, ed. Anagnostopolos, G., 526539. Malden: Wiley-Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDowell, J. 1997. “Deliberation and Moral Development in Aristotle’s Ethics.” In Aristotle, Kant, and the Stoics: Rethinking Happiness and Duty, ed. Engstrom, S. and Whiting, J., 2134. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Menn, S. 1992. “Aristotle and Plato on God as Nous and as the Good.Review of Metaphysics 45: 543573.Google Scholar
Menn, S. 2002. “Aristotle’s Definition of Soul and the Programme of the De Anima.Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 22: 83139.Google Scholar
Meyer, S. S. 2011. “Living for the Sake of an Ultimate End.” In Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics: A Critical Guide, ed. Miller, J., 4765. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Meyer, S. S. and Martin, A.. 2013. “Emotion and the Emotions.” In The Oxford Handbook to the History of Ethics, ed. Crisp, R., 638671. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Miller, F. D. 1995. Nature, Justice, and Rights in Aristotle’s Politics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Miller, F. D. 2013. “The Rule of Reason.” In The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle’s Politics, ed. Deslauriers, M. and Destrée, P., 3866. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, M. 1991. “Review of Aristotle on the Human Good.Political Theory 19: 109112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miner, R. 2009. Thomas Aquinas on the Passions: A Study of Summa Theologiae, 1a2ae 22–48. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mirus, C. V. 2004. “Aristotle’s Agathon.Review of Metaphysics 57: 515536.Google Scholar
Modrak, D. K. W. 1991. “The Nous-Body Problem in Aristotle.Review of Metaphysics 44: 755774.Google Scholar
Monan, J. D. 1968. Moral Knowledge and Methodology in Aristotle. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. [1903] 1993. Principia Ethica. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Moss, J. 2012. Aristotle on the Apparent Good: Perception, Phantasia, Thought, and Desire. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nagel, T. [1972] 1980. “Aristotle on Eudaimonia.” In Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics, ed. Rorty, A. O., 714. Berkeley: University of California Press. (Originally in Phronesis 17.)Google Scholar
Natali, C. 2001. The Wisdom of Aristotle, trans. Parks, G.. Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Natali, C. 2007. “Rhetorical and Scientific Aspects of the Nicomachean Ethics.Phronesis 52: 364381.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Needler, M. C. 1928. “The Aristotelian Protrepticus and the Developmental Treatment of the Aristotelian Ethics.Classical Philology 23: 280284.Google Scholar
Nielsen, K. M. 2015. “Aristotle on Principles in Ethics: Political Science as the Science of the Human Good.” In Bridging the Gap between Aristotle’s Science and Ethics, ed. Henry, D. and Nielsen, K. M., 2948. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nightingale, A. W. 1995. Genres in Dialogue: Plato and the Construct of Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nightingale, A. W. 2004. Spectacles of Truth in Classical Greek Philosophy: Theoria in Its Cultural Context. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
North, H. M. 1966. Sophrosyne: Self-Knowledge and Self-Restraint in Greek Literature. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
North, H. M. 1979. From Myth to Icon: Reflections of Greek Ethical Doctrine in Literature and Art. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. C. 1986. The Fragility of Goodness: Luck and Ethics in Greek Tragedy and Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. C. 1990. “Transcending Humanity.” In Love’s Knowledge: Essays on Life and Literature, 365391. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. C. 1994. The Therapy of Desire: Theory and Practice in Hellenistic Ethics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. C. 1995. “Aristotle on Human Nature and the Foundations of Ethics.” In World, Mind, and Ethics: Essays on the Ethical Philosophy of Bernard Williams, ed. Altham, J. E. J. and Harrison, R., 86131. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oakeshott, M. [1962] 1991. Rationalism in Politics and Other Essays. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.Google Scholar
Ober, J. 1995. “Greek Horoi: Artifactual Texts and the Contingency of Meaning.” In Methods in the Mediterranean: Historical and Archaeological Views of Texts and Archaeology (Mnemosyne supplement), ed. Small, D., 91123. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
Oderberg, D. 2010. “Whatever Is Changing Is Being Changed by Something Else’: A Reappraisal of Premise One of the First Way.In Mind, Method, and Morality: Essays in Honour of Anthony Kenny, ed. Cottingham, J. G. and Hacker, P., 140164. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Oehler, K. 1974. “Aristotle on Self-Knowledge.” Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society 118: 493506.Google Scholar
Owen, G. E. L. 1965. “The Platonism of Aristotle.Proceedings of the British Academy 51: 125150.Google Scholar
Owens, J. 1962. The Doctrine of Being in the Aristotelian Metaphysics. Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies.Google Scholar
Owens, J. 1987. “Aristotle’s Notion of Wisdom.Apeiron 20: 116.Google Scholar
Pakaluk, M. 2011. “On the Unity of the Nicomachean Ethics.” In Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics: A Critical Guide, ed. Miller, J., 2344. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pangle, L. S. 2003. Aristotle and the Philosophy of Friendship. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pangle, T. L. 1987. “Introduction.” In The Roots of Political Philosophy: Ten Forgotten Socratic Dialogues. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Pearson, G. 2012. Aristotle on Desire. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pearson, G. 2014. “Courage and Temperance.” In The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, ed. Polansky, R., 110134. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pépin, J. 1971. Idées grecques sur l’homme et sur dieu. Paris: Les Belles Lettres.Google Scholar
Pradeau, J.-F. 1999. “Introduction.” In Platon: Alcibiade, trans. Marboeuf, C. and Pradeau, J.-F.. Paris: Flammarion.Google Scholar
Peterson, S. 1988. “Horos (Limit) in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics.Phronesis 33: 233250.Google Scholar
Polansky, R. 2007. Aristotle’s De Anima. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Price, A. W. 1989. Love and Friendship in Plato and Aristotle. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Purinton, J. S. 1998. “Aristotle’s Definition of Happiness (NE 1.7, 1098a16-18).Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 16: 259297.Google Scholar
Rabinowitz, W. G. 1957. Aristotle’s Protrepticus and the Sources of Its Reconstruction. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Randall, J. H. Jr. 1960. Aristotle. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Reeve, C. D. C. 2012. Action, Contemplation, and Happiness: An Essay on Aristotle. Cambridge and London: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Renaud, F. and Tarrant, H.. 2015. The Platonic Alcibiades I: The Dialogue and Its Ancient Reception. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Richardson, H. S. 1992. “Degrees of Finality and the Highest Good in Aristotle.Journal of the History of Philosophy 30: 327352.Google Scholar
Richardson, J. Aristotle’s Teleologies. Unpublished manuscript. as.nyu.edu/docs/IO/1174/aristel.pdf.Google Scholar
Rider, B. A. 2011. “Self-Care, Self-Knowledge, and the Alcibiades I.Epoche 15: 395413.Google Scholar
Riggs, W. 2003. “Understanding Virtue and the Virtue of Understanding.” In Intellectual Virtues: Perspectives from Ethics and Epistemology, ed. DePaul, M. and Zagzebski, L., 203226. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roche, T. D. 1988a. “On the Alleged Metaphysical Foundation of Aristotle’s Ethics.Ancient Philosophy 8: 4962.Google Scholar
Roche, T. D. 1988b. “The Perfect Happiness.” Southern Journal of Philosophy 27 supp., Aristotle’s Ethics, 103125.Google Scholar
Roche, T. D. 1988c. “Ergon and Eudaimonia in Nicomachean Ethics I: Reconsidering the Intellectualist Interpretation.Journal of the History of Philosophy 26: 175194.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roche, T. D. 2014. “Happiness and the External Goods.” In The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, ed. Polansky, R., 3463. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rogers, K. 1993. “Aristotle’s Conception of To Kalon.Ancient Philosophy 13: 355371.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rogers, K. 1994. “Aristotle on the Motive of Courage.The Southern Journal of Philosophy 32: 303313.Google Scholar
Roochnik, D. 2009. “What Is Theoria?: Nicomachean Ethics Book 10.7–8.Classical Philology 104: 6982.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roochnik, D. Unpublished. “Reading Aristotle’s Writing.”Google Scholar
Rorty, A. O. 1980. “The Place of Contemplation in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics.” In Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics, ed. Rorty, A. O., 377394. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Rue, R. 1993. “The Philosopher in Flight: The Digression (172c–177c) in Plato’s Theaetetus.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 11: 71100.Google Scholar
Russell, D. C. 2004. “Virtue as ‘Likeness to God’ in Plato and Seneca.Journal of the History of Philosophy 42: 241260.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salkever, S. G. 1990. Finding the Mean: Theory and Practice in Aristotelian Political Philosophy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Salmieri, G. 2009. “Aristotle’s Non-‘Dialectical’ Methodology in the Nicomachean Ethics.” Ancient Philosophy 29: 311335.Google Scholar
Scheiter, K. 2013. “Review of Giles Pearson, Aristotle on Desire.Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. http://ndpr.nd.edu/news/39579-aristotle-on-desire/.Google Scholar
Schleiermacher, F. 1836. Introductions to the Dialogues of Plato, trans. Dobson, W.. Cambridge: J. & J.J. Deighton.Google Scholar
Schollmeier, P. 1994. Other Selves: Aristotle on Personal and Political Friendship. Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Scott, D. 1999. “Aristotle on Well-Being and Intellectual Contemplation: Primary and Secondary Eudaimonia.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplement 73: 224242.Google Scholar
Scott, D. 2015. Levels of Argument: A Comparative Study of Plato’s Republic and Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. 1999. “The Ideal of Godlikeness.” In Plato 2: Ethics, Politics, Religion, and the Soul, ed. Fine, G., 309328. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Seggiaro, C. 2012. “Los conceptos aristotélicos de ἐπιστήμη y σοφία en la Metafísica A-a y su correlato en el Protréptico.Nova Tellvs 30: 4374.Google Scholar
Sheffield, F. C. C. 2006. Plato’s Symposium: The Ethics of Desire. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sherman, N. 1987. “Aristotle on Friendship and the Shared Life.Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 47: 589613.Google Scholar
Sherman, T. P. 2002. “Human Happiness and the Role of Philosophical Wisdom in the Nicomachean Ethics.” International Philosophical Quarterly 42: 467492.Google Scholar
Sherman, T. P. 2006. “Wisdom and Action-Guidance in the Agent-Based Virtue Ethics of Aristotle.American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 80: 481506.Google Scholar
Shields, C. 2007. Aristotle. London and New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shields, C. 2011. “Perfecting Pleasures: The Metaphysics of Pleasure in Nicomachean Ethics x.” In Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics: A Critical Guide, ed. Miller, J., 191210. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Shields, C. 2015. “The Science of Soul.” In Bridging the Gap between Aristotle’s Science and Ethics, ed. Henry, D. and Nielsen, K. M., 232253. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Simpson, P. 2001. “Aristotle’s Idea of the Self.Journal of Value Inquiry 35: 309324.Google Scholar
Simpson, P. 2013b. “Aristotle’s Ethica Eudemia 1220b10-11 ἐν τοῖς ἀπηλλαγμένοις and De Virtutibus et Vitiis.Classical Quarterly 63: 651659.Google Scholar
Smith, N. D. 2004. “Did Plato Write the Alcibiades?Apeiron 37: 93108.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, T. W. 2001. Revaluing Ethics: Aristotle’s Dialectical Pedagogy. Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Sorabji, R. 1964. “Function.The Philosophical Quarterly 14: 289302.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sparshott, F. 1982. “Aristotle’s Ethics and Plato’s Republic: A Structural Comparison.Dialogue 21: 483499.Google Scholar
Sprague, R. K. 1972. “A Parallel with de Anima III, 5.Phronesis 17: 250251.Google Scholar
Stern, P. 2008. Knowledge and Politics in Plato’s Theaetetus. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Stern-Gillet, S. 1995. Aristotle’s Philosophy of Friendship. Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Striker, G. 1996. “Emotions in Context: Aristotle’s Treatment of the Passions in the Rhetoric and His Moral Psychology.” In Essays on Aristotle’s Rhetoric, ed. Rorty, A. O., 286302. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Tuozzo, T. M. 1992. “Contemplation, the Noble, and the Mean: The Standard of Moral Virtue in Aristotle’s Ethics.” In Aristotle, Virtue, and the Mean, ed. Bosley, R., Shiner, R., and Sisson, J., 129154. Edmonton: Academic Printing and Publishing.Google Scholar
Urmson, J. O. [1973] 1980. “Aristotle’s Doctrine of the Mean.” In Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics, ed. Rorty, A. O., 157170. Berkeley: University of California Press. (Originally in American Philosophical Quarterly 10.)Google Scholar
Veatch, H. B. 1962. Rational Man: A Modern Interpretation of Aristotle’s Ethics. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Vernant, J.-P. 1996. Myth and Society in Ancient Greece. Trans. Lloyd, J.. New York: Zone Books.Google Scholar
Walker, M. D. 2010. “The Utility of Contemplation in Aristotle’s Protrepticus.Ancient Philosophy 30: 135153.Google Scholar
Walker, M. D. 2011. “Aristotle on Activity ‘According to the Best and Most Final’ Virtue.Apeiron 44: 91110.Google Scholar
Walker, M. D. 2013a. “Rehabilitating Theoretical Wisdom.” Journal of Moral Philosophy 10: 763787.Google Scholar
Walker, M. D. 2013b. “Review of Jon Miller (ed.), Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics: A Critical Guide.Polis 30: 176180.Google Scholar
Walker, M. D. 2014. “Aristotle on the Utility and Choiceworthiness of Friends.Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 96: 151182.Google Scholar
Walker, M. D. 2016. “Confucian Worries about the Aristotelian Sophos.” In Moral and Intellectual Virtues in Western and Chinese Philosophy: The Turn toward Virtue, ed. Mi, C., Slote, M., and Sosa, E., 196213. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Walker, M. D. 2017. “How Narrow is Aristotle’s Contemplative Ideal?” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 94: 558583.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walker, M. D. Forthcoming. “Aristotle on Wittiness.” In Laughter and Comedy in Ancient Philosophy, ed. Destrée, P. and Trivigno, F.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wareh, T. 2012. The Theory and Practice of Life: Isocrates and the Philosophers. Washington, DC: Center for Hellenic Studies.Google Scholar
Wedin, M. V. 1988. Mind and Imagination in Aristotle. New Haven and London: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Weiner, N. O. 1993. The Harmony of the Soul: Mental Health and Moral Virtue Reconsidered. Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
White, S. A. 1990. “Is Aristotelian Happiness a Good Life or the Best Life?Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 8: 97137.Google Scholar
White, S. A. 1992. Sovereign Virtue: Aristotle on the Relation between Happiness and Prosperity. Stanford: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Whiting, J. 1986. “Human Nature and Intellectualism in Aristotle.Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 68: 7095.Google Scholar
Whiting, J. 1988. “Aristotle’s Function Argument: A Defense.Ancient Philosophy 8: 3348.Google Scholar
Whiting, J. 1992. “Living Bodies.” In Essays on Aristotle’s De Anima, ed. Nussbaum, M. and Rorty, A. O., 7591. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Whiting, J. 2002. “Locomotive Soul: The Parts of the Soul in Aristotle’s Scientific Works.Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 22: 141200.Google Scholar
Whiting, J. 2006. “The Nicomachean Account of Philia.” In The Blackwell Companion to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, ed. Kraut, R., 276304. Malden: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Whiting, J. 2012. “The Pleasure of Thinking Together: Prolegomena to a Complete Reading of EE VII.12.” In The Eudemian Ethics on the Voluntary, Friendship, and Luck: The Sixth S.V. Keeling Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy, ed. Leigh, F., 77154. Leiden and Boston: Brill.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilkes, K. V. [1978] 1980. “The Good Man and the Good for Man in Aristotle’s Ethics.” In Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics, ed. Rorty, A. O., 341357. Berkeley: University of California Press. (Originally in Mind 87.)Google Scholar
Wilkes, K. V. 1988. Real People: Personal Identity without Thought Experiments. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Wilkes, K. V. 1992. “Psuchê versus the Mind.” In Essays on Aristotle’s De Anima, ed. Nussbaum, M. and Rorty, A. O., 109127. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992.Google Scholar
Wilkins, E. G. 1917. “Know Thyself” in Greek and Latin Literature. Menasha: George Banta.Google Scholar
Witt, C. 1996. “The Evolution of Developmental Interpretations of Aristotle.” In Aristotle’s Philosophical Development: Problems and Prospects, ed. Wians, W. O., 6782. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Wood, J. L. 2011. “Contemplating the Beautiful: The Practical Importance of Theoretical Excellence in Aristotle’s Ethics.Journal of the History of Philosophy 49: 391412.Google Scholar
Young, C. 1988. “Aristotle on Temperance.Philosophical Review 97: 521542.Google Scholar
Yu, J. 2001. “Aristotle on Eudaimonia: After Plato’s Republic.History of Philosophy Quarterly 18: 115138.Google Scholar

Secondary Sources

Allan, D. J., ed. 1936. Aristotelis: De Caelo. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Balme, D. M., trans. and comm. [1972] 1999. Aristotle: De Partibus Animalium I and De Generatione Animalium I. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Balme, D. M., ed. 2002. Aristotle: Historia Animalium Volume I: Books I–X. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Barnes, J., ed. 1984. The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation, 2 vols. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Bywater, I., ed. 1894. Aristotelis: Ethica Nicomachea. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chroust, A.-H., trans. and comm. 1964. Aristotle: Protrepticus – A Reconstruction. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Drossaart Lulofs, H. J., ed. 1965. Aristotelis: De Generatione Animalium. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Düring, I., ed. and comm. 1961. Aristotle’s Protrepticus: An Attempt at Reconstruction. Gothenburg: Studia Graeca et Latina Gothoburgensia.Google Scholar
Fritz, K. von and Kapp, E., ed. and trans. 1950. Aristotle’s Constitution of Athens and Related Texts. New York: Hafner.Google Scholar
Furth, M., trans. 1985. Aristotle: Metaphysics, Books Zeta, Eta, Theta, Iota (VII–X). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.Google Scholar
Hamlyn, D. W., trans. and comm. [1968] 1993. Aristotle: De Anima: Books II and III. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hett, W. S., ed. and trans. Aristotle: On the Soul, Parva Naturalia, On Breath. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Hicks, R. D., ed. and comm. 1907. Aristotle: De Anima. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Irwin, T. H., trans. and comm. 1999. Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics, 2nd edn. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.Google Scholar
Joachim, H. H., ed. and comm. 1926. Aristotle: On Coming-to-Be and Passing-Away. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Lennox, J. G., trans. and comm. 2001a. Aristotle: On the Parts of Animals. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Louis, P., ed. and trans. 1956. Aristote: Les parties des animaux. Paris: Les Belles Lettres.Google Scholar
Louis, P. 1973, ed. and trans. Aristote: Marche des animaux; Mouvement des animaux; Index des traités biologiques. Paris: Les Belles Lettres.Google Scholar
Louis, P. 1982, ed. and trans. Aristote: Météorologiques, 2 vols. Paris: Les Belles Lettres.Google Scholar
Louis, P. 1994, ed. and trans. Aristote: Problemes, 3 vols. Paris: Les Belles Lettres.Google Scholar
Mayhew, R., ed. and trans. 2011. Aristotle: Problems, 2 vols. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. C., ed. and comm. 1978. Aristotle’s De Motu Animalium. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Pakaluk, M., trans. and comm. 1999. Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics, Books VIII and IX. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Peck, A. L. and Forster, E. S., ed. and trans. 1937. Aristotle: Parts of Animals, Movement of Animals, Progression of Animals. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rackham, H., ed. and trans. 1926. Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rackham, H., ed. and trans. 1932. Aristotle: Politics. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rackham, H., ed. and trans. 1935. Aristotle: Athenian Constitution, Eudemian Ethics, Virtues and Vices. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Reeve, C. D. C., trans. and comm. 2013. Aristotle on Practical Wisdom: Nicomachean Ethics VI. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reeve, C. D. C, trans. and comm. 2014. Nicomachean Ethics. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D., ed. and comm. 1924. Aristotle’s Metaphysics, 2 vols. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D., ed. 1950. Aristotelis: Physica. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D., ed. and comm. 1955. Aristotle: Parva Naturalia. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ross, W. D., ed. 1956. Aristotelis: De Anima. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D., ed. 1957. Aristotelis: Politica. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D., ed. 1958. Aristotelis: Topica et Sophistici Elenchi. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ross, W. D., ed. 1959. Aristotelis: Ars Rhetorica. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D., ed. 1964. Aristotelis: Analytica Priora et Posteriora. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sachs, J., trans. 2001. Aristotle’s De Anima and On Memory and Recollection. Santa Fe: Green Lion Press.Google Scholar
Sachs, J., trans. 2002. Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics. Newburyport: Focus.Google Scholar
Shields, C., trans. and comm. 2016. Aristotle: De Anima. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Simpson, P. L. P., trans. and comm. 2013a. The Eudemian Ethics of Aristotle. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers.Google Scholar
Simpson, P. L. P., trans. and comm. 2014. The Great Ethics of Aristotle. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers.Google Scholar
Susemihl, F., ed. 1883. Aristotelis: Magna Moralia. Leipzig: Teubner.Google Scholar
Taylor, C. C. W., trans. and comm. 2006. Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics, Books II–IV. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Tredennick, H., ed. and trans. 1933. Aristotle: Metaphysics: I–IX. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Tredennick, H., and Armstrong, G. C., ed. and trans. 1935. Aristotle: Metaphysics, X–XIV, Oeconomica, Magna Moralia. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Tredennick, H., and Forster, E. S., ed. and trans. 1960. Aristotle: Posterior Analytics and Topica. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Walzer, R. R. and Mingay, J. M., ed. 1991. Aristotelis: Ethica Eudemia. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Woods, M., trans. and comm. 1992. Aristotle: Eudemian Ethics, Books I, II, VIII, 2nd edn. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Bloom, A., trans. [1968] 1991. The Republic of Plato. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Burnet, J., ed. 1900–1907. Platonis: Opera, 5 vols. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M., ed. 1997. Plato: Collected Works. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.Google Scholar
Denyer, N., ed. and comm. 2001. Plato: Alcibiades. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lamb, W. R. M., ed. and trans. 1925. Plato: Lysis, Symposium, Gorgias. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Lamb, W. R. M., ed. and trans. 1927. Plato: Charmides, Alcibiades, Hipparchus, Lovers, Theages, Minos, Epinomis. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Lord, C. trans. 1987. “Alcibiades I.” In The Roots of Political Philosophy: Ten Forgotten Socratic Dialogues, ed. Pangle, T. L., 175221. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Rowe, C. J., ed. and trans. 1998. Plato: Symposium. Warminster: Aris & Phillips.Google Scholar
Alfarabi. [1962] 2001. Philosophy of Plato and Aristotle, trans. Mahdi, M.. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Alfarabi. 2001. The Harmonization of the Opinions of the Two Sages, Plato the Divine and Aristotle. In Alfarabi: The Political Writings, trans. Butterworth, C. E., 115168. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Aquinas, T. [1951] 1994. Commentary on Aristotle’s De Anima, trans. Foster, K. and Humphries, S.. Notre Dame: Dumb Ox Books.Google Scholar
Aquinas, T. [1964] 2003. Commentary on Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, trans. Litzinger, C.J.. Notre Dame: Dumb Ox Books.Google Scholar
Aquinas, T. [1920] 2006. The Summa Theologica of St. Thomas Aquinas, trans. The Fathers of the English Dominican Province. URL: http://www.newadvent.org/summa/.Google Scholar
Caston, V., trans. and comm. 2012. Alexander of Aphrodisias: On the Soul, Part I, Soul as Form of the Body, Parts of the Soul, Nourishment, and Perception. London: Bristol Classical Press.Google Scholar
des Places, É., ed. and trans. 1989. Jamblique: Protreptique. Paris: Les Belles Lettres.Google Scholar
Diels, H. and Kranz, W., ed. 1951. Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker. Berlin: Weidmann.Google Scholar
Dooley, W. E., trans. and comm. 1989. Alexander of Aphrodisias: On Aristotle’s Metaphysics 1. London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
Einarson, B. and Link, G. K. K., ed. and trans. Theophrastus: De Causis Plantarum I. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Fackenheim, E. L. 1945. “A Treatise on Love by Ibn Sina” (with translation). Mediaeval Studies 7: 208228.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Festa, N., ed. 1891. Iamblichi De Communi Mathematica Scientia. Leipzig: Teubner.Google Scholar
Griffin, M., trans. and comm. 2015. Olympiodorus: Life of Plato and On Plato First Alcibiades 1–9. London: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
Hicks, R. D., ed. and trans. 1925. Diogenes Laertius: Lives of the Eminent Philosophers I–II. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Jones, W. H. S., ed. and trans. 1931. Hippocrates, vol. 4. London: William Heinemann.Google Scholar
Marchant, E. C., ed. and trans. 1938. Xenophon: Memorabilia, Oeconomicus, Symposium, Apology. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Norlin, G., ed. and trans. 1929. Isocrates, 2 vols. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
O’Neill, W., trans. and comm. 1971. Proclus: Alcibiades I: A Translation and Commentary, 2nd ed. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Perrin, B., ed. and trans. 1916. Plutarch’s Lives: vol. iv. London: William Heinemann.Google Scholar
Pistelli, H. G. 1888. Iamblichi Protrepticus. Leipzig: Teubner.Google Scholar
Relihan, J. C., trans. and comm. 2001. Boethius: Consolation of Philosophy. Indianapolis and Cambridge: Hackett Publishing.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D. and Fobes, F. H., ed. and trans. 1967. Theophrastus: Metaphysics. Hildesheim: Georg Olms Verlagsbuchhandlung.Google Scholar
Todd, R. B., trans. and comm. 1996. Themistius: On Aristotle on the Soul. London: Bristol Classical Press.Google Scholar
Van Hook, L., ed. and trans. 1945. Isocrates III. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Achtenberg, D. [1988] 1995. “Human Being, Beast and God: The Place of Human Happiness According to Aristotle and Some Twentieth-Century Philosophers.” In The Crossroads of Norm and Nature: Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics and Metaphysics, ed. Sim, M., 2950. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield. (Originally in The St. John’s Review 38.)Google Scholar
Achtenberg, D. 2002. Cognition of Value in Aristotle’s Ethics: Promise of Enrichment, Threat of Destruction. Albany: State University of New York Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ackrill, J. L. [1974] 1980. “Aristotle on Eudaimonia.” In Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics, ed. Rorty, A. O., 1533. Berkeley: University of California Press. (Originally in Proceedings of the British Academy 60.)Google Scholar
Allan, D. J. 1975. “A Passage from Iamblichus in Praise of the Contemplative Life.” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 57: 246268.Google Scholar
Annas, J. 1981. An Introduction to Plato’s Republic. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Annas, J. 1985. “Self-Knowledge in Early Plato.” In Platonic Investigations, ed. O’Meara, D., 111138. Washington, D.C.: Catholic University of America Press.Google Scholar
Annas, J. 1993. The Morality of Happiness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Annas, J. 1999. Platonic Ethics, Old and New. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Anscombe, G. E. M. 1953. “The Principle of Individuation.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 27 supp.: 8395.Google Scholar
Armstrong, J. M. 2004. “After the Ascent: Plato on Becoming Like God.Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 26: 171183.Google Scholar
Arnhart, L. 1998. Darwinian Natural Right: The Biological Ethics of Human Nature. Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Aubenque, P. 1963. Le prudence chez Aristote. Presses Universitaires de France.Google Scholar
Baehr, J. 2012. “Two Types of Wisdom.Acta Analytica 27: 8197.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baehr, J. 2014. “Sophia.” In Virtues and Their Vices, ed. Timpe, K. and Boyd, C., 303323. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Balme, D. M. 1987. “Teleology and Necessity.” In Philosophical Issues in Aristotle’s Biology, ed. Gotthelf, A. and Lennox, J. G., 275285. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Balot, R. K. 2014. Courage in the Democratic Polis: Ideology and Critique in Classical Athens. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Barnes, J. 1995. “Life and Work.” In The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle, 126. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Barnes, J. [1997] 2015. “Roman Aristotle.” In Mantissa: Essays in Ancient Philosophy IV, ed. Bonelli, M., 408478. Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Originally in Philosophia Togata II, ed. J. Barnes and M. Griffin.)Google Scholar
Baynham, E. J. and Tarrant, H.. 2012. “Fourth-Century Politics and the Date of the Alcibiades I.” In Alcibiades and the Socratic Lover-Educator, ed. Johnson, M. and Tarrant, H., 215222. London: Bristol Classical Press.Google Scholar
Beere, J. 2009. Doing and Being: An Interpretation of Aristotle’s Metaphysics Theta. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bluck, R. S. 1953. “The Origin of the Greater Alcibiades.Classical Quarterly 47: 4652.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bobonich, C. 2007. “Why Should Philosophers Rule: Plato’s Republic and Aristotle’s Protrepticus.Social Philosophy & Policy 24: 153175.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bodéüs, R. 2000. Aristotle and the Theology of the Living Immortals, trans. Garrett, J.. Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Bodnar, I. 2015. “The Problemata Physica: An Introduction.” In The Aristotelian Problemata Physica, ed. Mayhew, R., 19. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
Bostock, D. 2000. Aristotle’s Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Brague, R. 1988. Aristote et le question du monde: Essai sur le contexte cosmologique et anthropologique de l’ontologie. Presses Universitaires de France.Google Scholar
Brink, D. O. 1999. “Eudaimonism, Love and Friendship, and Political Community.” In Human Flourishing, ed. Paul, E. F., Miller, F. D. Jr., and Paul, J., 252289. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broadie, S. 1991. Ethics with Aristotle. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Broadie, S. 1999. “Aristotle’s Elusive Summum Bonum.” In Human Flourishing, ed. Paul, E. F., Miller, F., and Paul, J., 233251. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, E. 2000. “Justice and Compulsion for Plato’s Philosopher-Rulers.Ancient Philosophy 20: 117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, E. 2004. “Minding the Gap in Plato’s Republic.Philosophical Studies 117: 275302.Google Scholar
Brown, E. 2006. “Wishing for Fortune, Choosing Activity: Aristotle on External Goods and Happiness.Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 22: 221256.Google Scholar
Brown, E. 2012. “The Unity of the Soul in Plato’s Republic.” In Plato and the Divided Self, ed. Barney, R., Brennan, T., and Brittain, C., 5373. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, L. 1997. “What Is the ‘Mean Relative to Us’ in Aristotle’s Ethics?Phronesis 42: 7793.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burnyeat, M. F. 1980. “Aristotle on Learning to Be Good.” In Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics, ed. Rorty, A. O., 6992. Berkeley: University of California Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burnyeat, M. F. 2008. Aristotle’s Divine Intellect: The Aquinas Lecture, 28. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press.Google Scholar
Bush, S. S. 2008. “Divine and Human Happiness in Nicomachean Ethics.Philosophical Review 117: 4975.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bywater, I. 1869. “On a Lost Dialogue of Aristotle.Journal of Philology 2: 5569.Google Scholar
Cambiano, G. 2012. “The Desire to Know: Metaphysics A 1.In Aristotle’s Metaphysics A: Symposium Aristotelicum, ed. Steele, C. and Primavesi, O., 142. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Case, T. (1910) 1996. “Aristotle.” In Aristotle’s Philosophical Development: Problems and Prospects, ed. Wians, W. O., 140. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield. (Originally in Encyclopedia Brittanica.)Google Scholar
Casebeer, W. D. 2003. Natural Ethical Facts: Evolution, Connectionism, and Moral Cognition. Cambridge and London: The MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caston, V. 1996. “Aristotle on the Relation of the Intellect to the Body: Commentary on Broadie.Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 12: 170192.Google Scholar
Caston, V. 1999. “Aristotle’s Two Intellects: A Modest Proposal.Phronesis 44: 199227.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caston, V. 2006. “Aristotle’s Psychology.” In A Companion to Ancient Philosophy, ed. Gill, M. L. and Pellegrin, P., 316346. Malden: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Caston, V. 2009. “Phantasia and Thought.” In A Companion to Aristotle, ed. Anagastopolos, G., 322334. Malden: Wiley-Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cates, D. F. 2009. Aquinas on the Emotions: A Religious-Ethical Inquiry. Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press.Google Scholar
Charles, D. 1999. “Aristotle on Well-Being and Intellectual Contemplation.Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 73 supp.: 205223.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Charlton, W. 1987. “Aristotle on the Place of Mind in Nature.In Philosophical Issues in Aristotle’s Biology, ed. Gotthelf, A. and Lennox, J. G., 408423. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chroust, A.-H. 1973. Aristotle: New Light on His Life and on Some of His Lost Works, vol. 1. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Clark, S. R. L. 1975. Aristotle’s Man: Speculations on Aristotelian Anthropology. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Code, A. 1984. “The Aporematic Approach to Primary Being in Metaphysics Z.Canadian Journal of Philosophy 14 supp.: 120.Google Scholar
Cohoe, C. 2014. “Nous in Aristotle’s De Anima.Philosophy Compass 9: 594604.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Collins, J. H. II. 2015. Exhortations to Philosophy: The Protreptics of Plato, Isocrates, and Aristotle. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Conway, D. 2000. The Rediscovery of Wisdom: From Here to Antiquity in Quest of Sophia. Houndmills and London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. [1973] 1999. “The Magna Moralia and Aristotle’s Moral Philosophy.” In Reason and Emotion, 195211. Princeton: Princeton University Press. (Originally in American Journal of Philology 94.)Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. [1975] 1986. Reason and the Human Good in Aristotle. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing. (Originally Harvard University Press.)Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. [1977] 1999. “Friendship and the Good in Aristotle.” In Reason and Emotion, 336355. Princeton: Princeton University Press. (Originally in Philosophical Review 86.)Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. [1985] 1999. “Aristotle on the Goods of Fortune.” In Reason and Emotion, 292311. Princeton: Princeton University Press. (Originally in Philosophical Review 94.)Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. [1987] 1999. “Contemplation and Happiness: A Reconsideration.” In Reason and Emotion, 212236. Princeton: Princeton University Press. (Originally in Synthese 72.)Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. [1988] 1999. “Some Remarks on Aristotle’s Moral Psychology.” In Reason and Emotion, 237252. Princeton: Princeton University Press. (Originally in Southern Journal of Philosophy 27 supplement.)Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. 1996. “An Aristotelian Theory of the Emotions.” In Essays on Aristotle’s Rhetoric, ed. Rorty, A. O., 238257. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. [1996] 1999. “Reason, Moral Virtue, and Moral Value.” In Reason and Emotion, 253280. Princeton: Princeton University Press. (Originally in Rationality in Greek Thought, ed. M. Frede and G. Striker.)Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. [2003] 2004. “Plato and Aristotle on ‘Finality’ and ‘(Self-)Sufficiency.” In Knowledge, Nature, and the Good: Essays in Ancient Philosophy, 270308. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. 2004. “Plato, Isocrates, and Cicero on the Independence of Oratory from Philosophy.” In Knowledge, Nature, and the Good: Essays in Ancient Philosophy, 6580. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. 2009. “Nicomachean Ethics VII.1–2: Introduction, Method, Puzzles.” In Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics, Book VII Symposium Aristotelicum, ed. Natali, C., 939. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. 2010. “Political Community and the Highest Good.” In Being, Nature, and Life in Aristotle: Essays in Honor of Allan Gotthelf, ed. Lennox, J. G. and Bolton, R., 212264. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Corcilius, K. 2011. “Aristotle’s Definition of Non-Rational Pleasure and Pain and Desire.” In Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics: A Critical Guide, ed. Miller, J., 117143. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Corcilius, K. and Gregoric, P.. 2010. “Separability vs. Difference: Parts and Capacities of the Soul in Aristotle.Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 39: 81120.Google Scholar
Courcelle, P. 1974. Connais-toi toi-meme de Socrate a Saint Bernard, vol. I. Paris: Etudes Augustiniennes.Google Scholar
Curzer, H. J. 1991. “Aristotle’s Much Maligned Megalopsychos.Australasian Journal of Philosophy 69: 131151.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Curzer, H. J. 2012. Aristotle & the Virtues. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dahl, N. 2011. “Contemplation and Eudaimonia in the Nicomachean Ethics.” In Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics: A Critical Guide, ed. Miller, J., 6691. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Defourny, P. 1978. “Contemplation in Aristotle’s Ethics.” In Articles on Aristotle. vol. 2, Ethics and Politics, ed. Barnes, J., Schofield, M., and Sorabji, R., 104112. New York: St. Martin’s Press.Google Scholar
De Haas, F. 2009. “Know Thyself: Plato and Aristotle on Awareness.” In Ancient Perspectives on Aristotle’s De Anima, ed. Van Riel, G. and Destreé, P., 4969. Leuven: Leuven University Press.Google Scholar
Den Uyl, D. 1991. The Virtue of Prudence. New York: Peter Lang.Google Scholar
Depew, D. J. 1981. “Aristotle’s De Anima and Marx’s Theory of Man.Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal 8: 133185.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Depew, D. J. 1995. “Humans and Other Political Animals in Aristotle’s History of Animals.Phronesis 40: 156181.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Depew, D. J. 2004. “The Inscription of Isocrates into Aristotle’s Practical Philosophy.” In Isocrates and Civic Education, ed. Poulakos, T. and Depew, D., 157185. Austin: University of Texas Press.Google Scholar
Detienne, M. 1982. “Between Beasts and Gods.” In Myth, Religion, and Society, ed. Gordon, R. L., 215228. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Diamond, E. 2014. “Aristotle’s Appropriation of Plato’s Sun Analogy in De Anima.Apeiron 47: 356389.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Diamond, E. 2015. Mortal Imitations of Divine Life: The Nature of the Soul in Aristotle’s De Anima. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
Elders, L. 1972. Aristotle’s Theology: A Commentary on Book Λ of the Metaphysics. Assen: Van Gorcum.Google Scholar
Everson, S. 1998. “Aristotle on Nature and Value.” In Ethics: Companions to Ancient Thought 4, ed. Everson, S., 77106. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feser, E. 2013. “The New Atheists and the Cosmological Argument.Midwest Studies in Philosophy 37: 154177.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foot, P. [2001] 2003. Natural Goodness. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Fossheim, H. 2011. “Justice in the Nicomachean Ethics Book V.” In Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics: A Critical Guide, ed. Miller, J., 254275. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Foucault, M. [2001] 2005. The Hermeneutics of the Subject: Lectures at the College de France, 1981–1982. Ed. Gros, F. and trans. Burchell, G.. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Frankena, W. K. 1939. “The Naturalistic Fallacy.Mind 48: 464477.Google Scholar
Frankfurt, H. [1992] 1999. “The Usefulness of Final Ends.” In Necessity, Volition, and Love, 8294. New York: Cambridge University Press. (Originally in Iyyun 41.)Google Scholar
Frede, D. 2014. “A Swarm of Virtues: On the Unity and Completeness of Aristotle’s Scheme of Character-Virtues.” In Strategies of Argument: Essays in Ancient Ethics, Epistemology, and Logic, ed. Lee, M., 83103. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Frede, M. 1992. “On Aristotle’s Conception of Soul.” In Essays on Aristotle’s De Anima, ed. Nussbaum, M. C. and Rorty, A. O., 93107. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Frede, M. 2008. “Aristotle’s Account of the Origins of Philosophy.” In The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy, ed. Curd, P. and Graham, D. W., 501529. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Freeland, C. A. 1987. “Aristotle on Bodies, Matter, and Potentiality.” In Philosophical Issues in Aristotle’s Biology, ed. Gotthelf, A. and Lennox, J. G., 392407. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Freeland, C. A. 1994. “Aristotle on Perception, Appetition, and Self-Motion.” In Self-Movers, ed. Gill, M. L. and Lennox, J. G., 3563. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Freudenthal, G. 1995. Aristotle’s Theory of Material Substance: Heat and Pneuma, Form and Soul. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Friedländer, P. 1964. Plato, vol. 2, trans. Meyerhoff, H.. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Furth, M. 1988. Substance, Form, and Psyche: An Aristotelean Metaphysics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gadamer, H.-G. 1928. “Der Aristotelische Protreptikos und die Entwicklungsgeschichtliche Betrachtung der Aristotelischen Ethik.Hermes 63: 138164.Google Scholar
Gadamer, H.-G. 1986. The Idea of the Good in Platonic-Aristotelian Philosophy. Trans. Smith, P. C.. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Garver, E. 2006. Confronting Aristotle’s Ethics: Ancient and Modern Morality. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Gauthier, R. A. and Jolif, J. Y., 2002. L’Éthique à Nicomaque, 2nd edn. Louvain-la-Neuve: Éditions Peeters.Google Scholar
Gentzler, J. 2004. “The Attractions and Delights of Goodness.Philosophical Quarterly 54: 353367.Google Scholar
Gerson, L. P. 2005. Aristotle and Other Platonists. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Gill, C. 2006. The Structured Self in Hellenistic and Roman Thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gill, M. L. 1989a. “Aristotle on Matters of Life and Death.Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium on Ancient Philosophy 5: 187205.Google Scholar
Gill, M. L. 1989b. Aristotle on Substance: The Paradox of Unity. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Gotthelf, A. 1975. “Aristotle’s Conception of Final Causality.” Ph.D. dissertation, Columbia University.Google Scholar
Gotthelf, A. [1985] 2012. “Notes Toward a Study of Substance and Essence in Aristotle’s Parts of Animals II-IV.” In Teleology, First Principles, and Scientific Method in Aristotle’s Biology, 217240. Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Originally in Aristotle on Nature and Living Things.)Google Scholar
Gotthelf, A. [1987] 2012. “Aristotle’s Conception of Final Causality.” In Teleology, First Principles, and Scientific Method in Aristotle’s Biology, 344. Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Originally in Philosophical Issues in Aristotle’s Biology.)Google Scholar
Gotthelf, A. [1988] 2012. “The Place of the Good in Aristotle’s Natural Teleology.” In Teleology, First Principles, and Scientific Method in Aristotle’s Biology, 344. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 4566. (Originally in Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium on Ancient Philosophy 4.)Google Scholar
Gottlieb, P. 2009. The Virtue of Aristotle’s Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Gottlieb, P. and Sober, E.. Forthcoming. “Aristotle on ‘Nature Does Nothing in Vain.’” History of Philosophy of Science.Google Scholar
Greenwood, L. H. G., ed., trans., and comm. 1909. Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics Book VI. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Grene, M. 1963. A Portrait of Aristotle. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Grönroos, G. 2007. “Listening to Reason in Aristotle’s Moral Psychology.Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 32: 251271.Google Scholar
Hackforth, R. 1950. “Immortality in Plato’s Symposium.The Classical Review 64: 4345.Google Scholar
Halper, E. 1993. “The Rational Basis of Aristotle’s Virtue.” In Form and Reason: Essays in Metaphysics, 5773. Albany: State University of Albany Press.Google Scholar
Halper, E. 1995. “The Substance of Aristotle’s Ethics.” In The Crossroads of Norm and Nature: Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics and Metaphysics, ed. Sim, M., 328. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Hardie, W. F. R. 1965. “The Final Good in Aristotle’s Ethics.Philosophy 40: 277295.Google Scholar
Hardie, W. F. R. 1979. “Aristotle on the Best Life for a Man.Philosophy 54: 3550.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hare, J. E. 2007. God and Morality: A Philosophical History. Malden: Blackwell Publishing.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hegel, G. W. F. 1894. Lectures on the History of Philosophy, vol. II, trans. Haldane, E. S. and Simson, F. H.. London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trübner.Google Scholar
Heinaman, R. 2000. “Cooper on Ancient Ethics.Polis 17: 161185.Google Scholar
Henry, D. 2013. “Optimality and Teleology in Aristotle’s Natural Science.Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 45: 225263.Google Scholar
Henry, D. and Nielsen, K. M.. 2015. “Introduction.” In Bridging the Gap between Aristotle’s Science and Ethics, 125. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horster, M. 2010. “Religious Landscape and Sacred Ground: Relationships between Space and Cult in the Greek World.Revue de l’histoire des religions 4: 435458.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hughes, G. J. 2001. Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Aristotle on Ethics. London and New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Hursthouse, R. 1999. On Virtue Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hutchinson, D. S., 1988. “Review of Aristotle: The Power of Perception by Deborah Modrak.Phoenix 42: 7677.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hutchinson, D. S. and Johnson, M. R.. 2005. “Authenticating Aristotle’s Protrepticus.Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 29: 193294.Google Scholar
Hutchinson, D. S. and Johnson, M. R.. 2014. “Protreptic Aspects of the Nicomachean Ethics.” In The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, ed. Polansky, R., 383409. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hutchinson, D. S. and Johnson, M. R.. Unpublished work A. Aristotle: Protrepticus, with Commentary. www.protrepticus.info.Google Scholar
Hutchinson, D. S. and Johnson, M. R.Unpublished work B. “The Antidosis of Isocrates and Aristotle’s Protrepticus.” www.protrepticus.info.Google Scholar
Inglis, K. 2014. “Philosophical Virtue: In Defense of the Grand End.” In The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, ed. Polansky, R., 263287. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Irwin, T. H. 1980. “The Metaphysical and Psychological Basis of Aristotle’s Ethics.” In Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics, ed. Rorty, A. O., 3553. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Inglis, K. 1988. Aristotle’s First Principles. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Inglis, K. 1991. “The Structure of Aristotelian Happiness.Ethics 101: 382391.Google Scholar
Inglis, K. 1995. Plato’s Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Inglis, K. 2007. The Development of Ethics: A Historical and Critical Study, vol. 1. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Inglis, K. 2009. The Development of Ethics: A Historical and Critical Study, vol. 3. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Inglis, K. 2011. “Beauty and Morality in Aristotle.” In Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics: A Critical Guide, ed. Miller, J., 239253. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Inglis, K. 2012. “Conceptions of Happiness in the Nicomachean Ethics.” In The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle, ed. Shields, C., 495528. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ivanhoe, P. J. and Van Norden, B.. 2005. Readings in Classical Chinese Philosophy, 2nd ed. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.Google Scholar
Jaeger, W. 1957. “Aristotle’s Use of Medicine as Model of Method in His Ethics.” Journal of Hellenic Studies 77–78: 5461.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jaeger, W. 1962. Aristotle: Fundamentals of the History of His Development, 2nd ed., trans. Robinson, R.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Jirsa, J. 2009. “Authenticity of the Alcibiades I: Some Reflections.Listy filologické 132: 225244.Google Scholar
Johansen, T. K. 2012. The Powers of Aristotle’s Soul. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Johnson, D. M. 1999. “God as the True Self: Plato’s Alcibiades I.Ancient Philosophy 19: 119.Google Scholar
Johnson, M. R. 2005. Aristotle on Teleology. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnson, M. R. 2012. “The Medical Background of Aristotle’s Theory of Nature and Spontaneity.Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 27: 105152.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnson, M. R. 2015. “Aristotle’s Architectonic Sciences.” In Theory and Practice in Aristotle’s Natural Science, ed. Ebrey, D., 163186. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnstone, M. A. 2015. “Review of Anna Marmodoro, Aristotle on Perceiving Objects.” Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2015.01.06. http://ndpr.nd.edu/news/54985-aristotle-on-perceiving-objects/.Google Scholar
Jonas, H. [1966] 2001. The Phenomenon of Life: Toward a Philosophical Biology. Evanston: Northwestern University Press. (Originally Harper & Row.)Google Scholar
Kahn, C. H. 1981. “Aristotle and Altruism.Mind 90: 2040.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahn, C. H. 1985. “The Place of the Prime Mover in Aristotle’s Teleology.” In Aristotle on Nature and Living Things: Philosophical and Historical Studies, ed. Gotthelf, A., 183205. Pittsburgh: Mathesis Publications.Google Scholar
Karbowski, J. 2012. “Slaves, Women, and Aristotle’s Natural Teleology.Ancient Philosophy 32: 323353.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kenny, A. 1978. The Aristotelian Ethics: A Study of the Relationship Between the Eudemian and the Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Kenny, A. 1992. Aristotle on the Perfect Life. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keyt, D. [1978] 1983. “Intellectualism in Aristotle.” In Essays in Ancient Greek Philosophy, vol. 2, ed. Anton, J. and Preus, A., 346387. Albany: State University of Albany Press.Google Scholar
King, R. A. H. 2001. Aristotle on Life and Death. London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
Kosman, A. 1969. “Aristotle’s Definition of Motion.Phronesis 14: 4062.Google Scholar
Kosman, A. 1992. “What Does the Maker Mind Make?” In Essays on Aristotle’s De Anima, ed. Nussbaum, M. C. and Rorty, A. O., 343358. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Kosman, A. 2013. The Activity of Being: An Essay on Aristotle’s Ontology. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koziak, B. 2000. Retrieving Political Emotion: Thumos, Aristotle, and Gender. University Park, Pa.: Pennsylvania State University Press.Google Scholar
Kraut, R. 1989. Aristotle on the Human Good. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1989.Google Scholar
Kraut, R. 1993. “In Defense of the Grand End.Ethics 103: 361374.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kraut, R. 2002. Aristotle: Political Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kraut, R. 2013. “An Aesthetic Reading of Aristotle’s Ethics.” In Politeia in Greek and Roman Philosophy, ed. Harte, V. and Lane, M., 231250. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kraut, R. 2016. “Aristotle’s Ethics.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Zalta, E. N., http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/aristotle-ethics/.Google Scholar
Kullmann, W. 1991. “Man as a Political Animal in Aristotle.” In A Companion to Aristotle’s Politics, ed. Keyt, D. and Miller, F. D. Jr., 94117.Google Scholar
Lacrosse, J. 2007. “Some Remarks about a Meeting between Socrates and an Indian (Aristoxenus’ fragment 53).Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 89: 247263.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lachterman, D. R. 1990. “Did Aristotle ‘Develop’?: Reflections on Werner Jaeger’s Thesis.Revue de Philosophie Ancienne 8: 140.Google Scholar
Lai, K. L. 2008. An Introduction to Chinese Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lalonde, G. V. 1991. “Horoi.” In The Athenian Agora (Vol. 19): Inscriptions: Horoi, Poletai Records, and Leases of Public Lands, ed. Lalonde, G. V., Langdon, M. K., and Walbank, M. B., 551. Princeton: The American School of Classical Studies at Athens.Google Scholar
Lawrence, G. 1993. “Aristotle and the Ideal Life.Philosophical Review 102: 134.Google Scholar
Lear, G. R. 2004. Happy Lives and the Highest Good: An Essay on Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Lear, G. R. 2015. “Aristotle on Happiness and Long Life.” In The Quest for the Good Life: Ancient Philosophers on Happiness, ed. Rabbas, O., Emilsson, E. K., Fossheim, H., and Tuominen, M., 127145. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lear, J. 1988. Aristotle: The Desire to Understand. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lear, J. 2000. Happiness, Death, and the Remainder of Life. Cambridge and London: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Leighton, S. R. 1996. “Aristotle and the Emotions.In Essays on Aristotle’s Rhetoric, ed. Rorty, A. O., 206237. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Lennox, J. G. 1985. “Are Aristotelian Species Eternal?” In Aristotle on Nature and Living Things: Philosophical and Historical Studies, ed. Gotthelf, A., 6794. Pittsburgh: Mathesis Publications.Google Scholar
Lennox, J. G. 1999. “The Place of Mankind in Aristotle’s Zoology.Philosophical Topics 27: 116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lennox, J. G. [1999] 2015. “Aristotle on the Biological Roots of Virtue: The Natural History of Natural Virtue.” In Bridging the Gap between Aristotle’s Science and Ethics, ed. Henry, D. and Nielsen, K. M., 193213. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Originally in Biology and the Foundations of Ethics.)Google Scholar
Lennox, J. G. 2001b. “Nature Does Nothing in Vain.” In Aristotle’s Philosophy of Biology, 205223. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lennox, J. G. 2010. “Bios and Explanatory Unity in Aristotle’s Biology.” In Definition in Greek Philosophy, ed. Charles, D., 330356. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Leunissen, M. 2010. Explanation and Teleology in Aristotle’s Science of Nature. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leunissen, M. 2012. “Aristotle on Natural Character and Its Implications for Moral Development.Journal of the History of Philosophy 50: 507530.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leunissen, M. 2015. “Aristotle on Knowing Natural Science for the Sake of Living Well.” In Bridging the Gap between Aristotle’s Science and Ethics, ed. Henry, D. and Nielsen, K. M., 214231. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, F. A. 1995. “Self-Knowledge in Aristotle.Topoi 15: 3958.Google Scholar
Liddell, H. G. and Scott, R.. [1889] 2001. An Intermediate Greek-English Lexicon. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Linck, M. S. 2006. “The Harmony of Plato and Aristotle.Philosophy in the Contemporary World 13: 3844.Google Scholar
Lloyd, G. E. R. 2012. Being, Humanity, and Understanding: Studies in Ancient and Modern Societies. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lockwood, T. 2014. “Competing Ways of Life and Ring Composition (NE x 6–8).” In The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, ed. Polansky, R., 350369. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Long, R. T. 1999. “The Irrelevance of Responsibility.Social Philosophy and Policy 16: 118145.Google Scholar
Lord, C. 1982. Education and Culture in the Political Thought of Aristotle. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Lorenz, H. 2006. The Brute Within: Appetitive Desire in Plato and Aristotle. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
MacIntyre, A. 2006. “Rival Aristotles: Aristotle Against Some Modern Aristotelians.” In Ethics and Politics: Selected Essays, Volume 2, 2240. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Madigan, A. 2001. “Review of Richard Bodéüs, Aristotle and the Theology of the Living Immortals.” Bryn Mawr Classical Review. http://ccat.sas.upenn.edu/bmcr/2001/2001–02-29.html.Google Scholar
Mara, G. M. 1987. “The Role of Philosophy in Aristotle’s Political Science.Polity 19: 375401.Google Scholar
Matthews, G. 1992. “De Anima 2.2–4 and the Meaning of Life.” In Essays on Aristotle’s De Anima, ed. Nussbaum, M. and Rorty, A. O., 185193. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Mayhew, R. 2009. “Rulers and Ruled.” In A Companion to Aristotle, ed. Anagnostopolos, G., 526539. Malden: Wiley-Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDowell, J. 1997. “Deliberation and Moral Development in Aristotle’s Ethics.” In Aristotle, Kant, and the Stoics: Rethinking Happiness and Duty, ed. Engstrom, S. and Whiting, J., 2134. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Menn, S. 1992. “Aristotle and Plato on God as Nous and as the Good.Review of Metaphysics 45: 543573.Google Scholar
Menn, S. 2002. “Aristotle’s Definition of Soul and the Programme of the De Anima.Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 22: 83139.Google Scholar
Meyer, S. S. 2011. “Living for the Sake of an Ultimate End.” In Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics: A Critical Guide, ed. Miller, J., 4765. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Meyer, S. S. and Martin, A.. 2013. “Emotion and the Emotions.” In The Oxford Handbook to the History of Ethics, ed. Crisp, R., 638671. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Miller, F. D. 1995. Nature, Justice, and Rights in Aristotle’s Politics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Miller, F. D. 2013. “The Rule of Reason.” In The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle’s Politics, ed. Deslauriers, M. and Destrée, P., 3866. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, M. 1991. “Review of Aristotle on the Human Good.Political Theory 19: 109112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miner, R. 2009. Thomas Aquinas on the Passions: A Study of Summa Theologiae, 1a2ae 22–48. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mirus, C. V. 2004. “Aristotle’s Agathon.Review of Metaphysics 57: 515536.Google Scholar
Modrak, D. K. W. 1991. “The Nous-Body Problem in Aristotle.Review of Metaphysics 44: 755774.Google Scholar
Monan, J. D. 1968. Moral Knowledge and Methodology in Aristotle. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. [1903] 1993. Principia Ethica. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Moss, J. 2012. Aristotle on the Apparent Good: Perception, Phantasia, Thought, and Desire. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nagel, T. [1972] 1980. “Aristotle on Eudaimonia.” In Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics, ed. Rorty, A. O., 714. Berkeley: University of California Press. (Originally in Phronesis 17.)Google Scholar
Natali, C. 2001. The Wisdom of Aristotle, trans. Parks, G.. Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Natali, C. 2007. “Rhetorical and Scientific Aspects of the Nicomachean Ethics.Phronesis 52: 364381.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Needler, M. C. 1928. “The Aristotelian Protrepticus and the Developmental Treatment of the Aristotelian Ethics.Classical Philology 23: 280284.Google Scholar
Nielsen, K. M. 2015. “Aristotle on Principles in Ethics: Political Science as the Science of the Human Good.” In Bridging the Gap between Aristotle’s Science and Ethics, ed. Henry, D. and Nielsen, K. M., 2948. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nightingale, A. W. 1995. Genres in Dialogue: Plato and the Construct of Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nightingale, A. W. 2004. Spectacles of Truth in Classical Greek Philosophy: Theoria in Its Cultural Context. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
North, H. M. 1966. Sophrosyne: Self-Knowledge and Self-Restraint in Greek Literature. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
North, H. M. 1979. From Myth to Icon: Reflections of Greek Ethical Doctrine in Literature and Art. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. C. 1986. The Fragility of Goodness: Luck and Ethics in Greek Tragedy and Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. C. 1990. “Transcending Humanity.” In Love’s Knowledge: Essays on Life and Literature, 365391. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. C. 1994. The Therapy of Desire: Theory and Practice in Hellenistic Ethics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. C. 1995. “Aristotle on Human Nature and the Foundations of Ethics.” In World, Mind, and Ethics: Essays on the Ethical Philosophy of Bernard Williams, ed. Altham, J. E. J. and Harrison, R., 86131. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oakeshott, M. [1962] 1991. Rationalism in Politics and Other Essays. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.Google Scholar
Ober, J. 1995. “Greek Horoi: Artifactual Texts and the Contingency of Meaning.” In Methods in the Mediterranean: Historical and Archaeological Views of Texts and Archaeology (Mnemosyne supplement), ed. Small, D., 91123. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
Oderberg, D. 2010. “Whatever Is Changing Is Being Changed by Something Else’: A Reappraisal of Premise One of the First Way.In Mind, Method, and Morality: Essays in Honour of Anthony Kenny, ed. Cottingham, J. G. and Hacker, P., 140164. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Oehler, K. 1974. “Aristotle on Self-Knowledge.” Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society 118: 493506.Google Scholar
Owen, G. E. L. 1965. “The Platonism of Aristotle.Proceedings of the British Academy 51: 125150.Google Scholar
Owens, J. 1962. The Doctrine of Being in the Aristotelian Metaphysics. Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies.Google Scholar
Owens, J. 1987. “Aristotle’s Notion of Wisdom.Apeiron 20: 116.Google Scholar
Pakaluk, M. 2011. “On the Unity of the Nicomachean Ethics.” In Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics: A Critical Guide, ed. Miller, J., 2344. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pangle, L. S. 2003. Aristotle and the Philosophy of Friendship. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pangle, T. L. 1987. “Introduction.” In The Roots of Political Philosophy: Ten Forgotten Socratic Dialogues. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Pearson, G. 2012. Aristotle on Desire. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pearson, G. 2014. “Courage and Temperance.” In The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, ed. Polansky, R., 110134. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pépin, J. 1971. Idées grecques sur l’homme et sur dieu. Paris: Les Belles Lettres.Google Scholar
Pradeau, J.-F. 1999. “Introduction.” In Platon: Alcibiade, trans. Marboeuf, C. and Pradeau, J.-F.. Paris: Flammarion.Google Scholar
Peterson, S. 1988. “Horos (Limit) in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics.Phronesis 33: 233250.Google Scholar
Polansky, R. 2007. Aristotle’s De Anima. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Price, A. W. 1989. Love and Friendship in Plato and Aristotle. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Purinton, J. S. 1998. “Aristotle’s Definition of Happiness (NE 1.7, 1098a16-18).Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 16: 259297.Google Scholar
Rabinowitz, W. G. 1957. Aristotle’s Protrepticus and the Sources of Its Reconstruction. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Randall, J. H. Jr. 1960. Aristotle. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Reeve, C. D. C. 2012. Action, Contemplation, and Happiness: An Essay on Aristotle. Cambridge and London: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Renaud, F. and Tarrant, H.. 2015. The Platonic Alcibiades I: The Dialogue and Its Ancient Reception. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Richardson, H. S. 1992. “Degrees of Finality and the Highest Good in Aristotle.Journal of the History of Philosophy 30: 327352.Google Scholar
Richardson, J. Aristotle’s Teleologies. Unpublished manuscript. as.nyu.edu/docs/IO/1174/aristel.pdf.Google Scholar
Rider, B. A. 2011. “Self-Care, Self-Knowledge, and the Alcibiades I.Epoche 15: 395413.Google Scholar
Riggs, W. 2003. “Understanding Virtue and the Virtue of Understanding.” In Intellectual Virtues: Perspectives from Ethics and Epistemology, ed. DePaul, M. and Zagzebski, L., 203226. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roche, T. D. 1988a. “On the Alleged Metaphysical Foundation of Aristotle’s Ethics.Ancient Philosophy 8: 4962.Google Scholar
Roche, T. D. 1988b. “The Perfect Happiness.” Southern Journal of Philosophy 27 supp., Aristotle’s Ethics, 103125.Google Scholar
Roche, T. D. 1988c. “Ergon and Eudaimonia in Nicomachean Ethics I: Reconsidering the Intellectualist Interpretation.Journal of the History of Philosophy 26: 175194.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roche, T. D. 2014. “Happiness and the External Goods.” In The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, ed. Polansky, R., 3463. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rogers, K. 1993. “Aristotle’s Conception of To Kalon.Ancient Philosophy 13: 355371.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rogers, K. 1994. “Aristotle on the Motive of Courage.The Southern Journal of Philosophy 32: 303313.Google Scholar
Roochnik, D. 2009. “What Is Theoria?: Nicomachean Ethics Book 10.7–8.Classical Philology 104: 6982.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roochnik, D. Unpublished. “Reading Aristotle’s Writing.”Google Scholar
Rorty, A. O. 1980. “The Place of Contemplation in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics.” In Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics, ed. Rorty, A. O., 377394. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Rue, R. 1993. “The Philosopher in Flight: The Digression (172c–177c) in Plato’s Theaetetus.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 11: 71100.Google Scholar
Russell, D. C. 2004. “Virtue as ‘Likeness to God’ in Plato and Seneca.Journal of the History of Philosophy 42: 241260.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salkever, S. G. 1990. Finding the Mean: Theory and Practice in Aristotelian Political Philosophy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Salmieri, G. 2009. “Aristotle’s Non-‘Dialectical’ Methodology in the Nicomachean Ethics.” Ancient Philosophy 29: 311335.Google Scholar
Scheiter, K. 2013. “Review of Giles Pearson, Aristotle on Desire.Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. http://ndpr.nd.edu/news/39579-aristotle-on-desire/.Google Scholar
Schleiermacher, F. 1836. Introductions to the Dialogues of Plato, trans. Dobson, W.. Cambridge: J. & J.J. Deighton.Google Scholar
Schollmeier, P. 1994. Other Selves: Aristotle on Personal and Political Friendship. Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Scott, D. 1999. “Aristotle on Well-Being and Intellectual Contemplation: Primary and Secondary Eudaimonia.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplement 73: 224242.Google Scholar
Scott, D. 2015. Levels of Argument: A Comparative Study of Plato’s Republic and Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. 1999. “The Ideal of Godlikeness.” In Plato 2: Ethics, Politics, Religion, and the Soul, ed. Fine, G., 309328. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Seggiaro, C. 2012. “Los conceptos aristotélicos de ἐπιστήμη y σοφία en la Metafísica A-a y su correlato en el Protréptico.Nova Tellvs 30: 4374.Google Scholar
Sheffield, F. C. C. 2006. Plato’s Symposium: The Ethics of Desire. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sherman, N. 1987. “Aristotle on Friendship and the Shared Life.Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 47: 589613.Google Scholar
Sherman, T. P. 2002. “Human Happiness and the Role of Philosophical Wisdom in the Nicomachean Ethics.” International Philosophical Quarterly 42: 467492.Google Scholar
Sherman, T. P. 2006. “Wisdom and Action-Guidance in the Agent-Based Virtue Ethics of Aristotle.American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 80: 481506.Google Scholar
Shields, C. 2007. Aristotle. London and New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shields, C. 2011. “Perfecting Pleasures: The Metaphysics of Pleasure in Nicomachean Ethics x.” In Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics: A Critical Guide, ed. Miller, J., 191210. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Shields, C. 2015. “The Science of Soul.” In Bridging the Gap between Aristotle’s Science and Ethics, ed. Henry, D. and Nielsen, K. M., 232253. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Simpson, P. 2001. “Aristotle’s Idea of the Self.Journal of Value Inquiry 35: 309324.Google Scholar
Simpson, P. 2013b. “Aristotle’s Ethica Eudemia 1220b10-11 ἐν τοῖς ἀπηλλαγμένοις and De Virtutibus et Vitiis.Classical Quarterly 63: 651659.Google Scholar
Smith, N. D. 2004. “Did Plato Write the Alcibiades?Apeiron 37: 93108.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, T. W. 2001. Revaluing Ethics: Aristotle’s Dialectical Pedagogy. Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Sorabji, R. 1964. “Function.The Philosophical Quarterly 14: 289302.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sparshott, F. 1982. “Aristotle’s Ethics and Plato’s Republic: A Structural Comparison.Dialogue 21: 483499.Google Scholar
Sprague, R. K. 1972. “A Parallel with de Anima III, 5.Phronesis 17: 250251.Google Scholar
Stern, P. 2008. Knowledge and Politics in Plato’s Theaetetus. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Stern-Gillet, S. 1995. Aristotle’s Philosophy of Friendship. Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Striker, G. 1996. “Emotions in Context: Aristotle’s Treatment of the Passions in the Rhetoric and His Moral Psychology.” In Essays on Aristotle’s Rhetoric, ed. Rorty, A. O., 286302. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Tuozzo, T. M. 1992. “Contemplation, the Noble, and the Mean: The Standard of Moral Virtue in Aristotle’s Ethics.” In Aristotle, Virtue, and the Mean, ed. Bosley, R., Shiner, R., and Sisson, J., 129154. Edmonton: Academic Printing and Publishing.Google Scholar
Urmson, J. O. [1973] 1980. “Aristotle’s Doctrine of the Mean.” In Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics, ed. Rorty, A. O., 157170. Berkeley: University of California Press. (Originally in American Philosophical Quarterly 10.)Google Scholar
Veatch, H. B. 1962. Rational Man: A Modern Interpretation of Aristotle’s Ethics. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Vernant, J.-P. 1996. Myth and Society in Ancient Greece. Trans. Lloyd, J.. New York: Zone Books.Google Scholar
Walker, M. D. 2010. “The Utility of Contemplation in Aristotle’s Protrepticus.Ancient Philosophy 30: 135153.Google Scholar
Walker, M. D. 2011. “Aristotle on Activity ‘According to the Best and Most Final’ Virtue.Apeiron 44: 91110.Google Scholar
Walker, M. D. 2013a. “Rehabilitating Theoretical Wisdom.” Journal of Moral Philosophy 10: 763787.Google Scholar
Walker, M. D. 2013b. “Review of Jon Miller (ed.), Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics: A Critical Guide.Polis 30: 176180.Google Scholar
Walker, M. D. 2014. “Aristotle on the Utility and Choiceworthiness of Friends.Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 96: 151182.Google Scholar
Walker, M. D. 2016. “Confucian Worries about the Aristotelian Sophos.” In Moral and Intellectual Virtues in Western and Chinese Philosophy: The Turn toward Virtue, ed. Mi, C., Slote, M., and Sosa, E., 196213. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Walker, M. D. 2017. “How Narrow is Aristotle’s Contemplative Ideal?” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 94: 558583.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walker, M. D. Forthcoming. “Aristotle on Wittiness.” In Laughter and Comedy in Ancient Philosophy, ed. Destrée, P. and Trivigno, F.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wareh, T. 2012. The Theory and Practice of Life: Isocrates and the Philosophers. Washington, DC: Center for Hellenic Studies.Google Scholar
Wedin, M. V. 1988. Mind and Imagination in Aristotle. New Haven and London: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Weiner, N. O. 1993. The Harmony of the Soul: Mental Health and Moral Virtue Reconsidered. Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
White, S. A. 1990. “Is Aristotelian Happiness a Good Life or the Best Life?Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 8: 97137.Google Scholar
White, S. A. 1992. Sovereign Virtue: Aristotle on the Relation between Happiness and Prosperity. Stanford: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Whiting, J. 1986. “Human Nature and Intellectualism in Aristotle.Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 68: 7095.Google Scholar
Whiting, J. 1988. “Aristotle’s Function Argument: A Defense.Ancient Philosophy 8: 3348.Google Scholar
Whiting, J. 1992. “Living Bodies.” In Essays on Aristotle’s De Anima, ed. Nussbaum, M. and Rorty, A. O., 7591. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Whiting, J. 2002. “Locomotive Soul: The Parts of the Soul in Aristotle’s Scientific Works.Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 22: 141200.Google Scholar
Whiting, J. 2006. “The Nicomachean Account of Philia.” In The Blackwell Companion to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, ed. Kraut, R., 276304. Malden: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Whiting, J. 2012. “The Pleasure of Thinking Together: Prolegomena to a Complete Reading of EE VII.12.” In The Eudemian Ethics on the Voluntary, Friendship, and Luck: The Sixth S.V. Keeling Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy, ed. Leigh, F., 77154. Leiden and Boston: Brill.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilkes, K. V. [1978] 1980. “The Good Man and the Good for Man in Aristotle’s Ethics.” In Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics, ed. Rorty, A. O., 341357. Berkeley: University of California Press. (Originally in Mind 87.)Google Scholar
Wilkes, K. V. 1988. Real People: Personal Identity without Thought Experiments. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Wilkes, K. V. 1992. “Psuchê versus the Mind.” In Essays on Aristotle’s De Anima, ed. Nussbaum, M. and Rorty, A. O., 109127. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992.Google Scholar
Wilkins, E. G. 1917. “Know Thyself” in Greek and Latin Literature. Menasha: George Banta.Google Scholar
Witt, C. 1996. “The Evolution of Developmental Interpretations of Aristotle.” In Aristotle’s Philosophical Development: Problems and Prospects, ed. Wians, W. O., 6782. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Wood, J. L. 2011. “Contemplating the Beautiful: The Practical Importance of Theoretical Excellence in Aristotle’s Ethics.Journal of the History of Philosophy 49: 391412.Google Scholar
Young, C. 1988. “Aristotle on Temperance.Philosophical Review 97: 521542.Google Scholar
Yu, J. 2001. “Aristotle on Eudaimonia: After Plato’s Republic.History of Philosophy Quarterly 18: 115138.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Bibliography
  • Matthew D. Walker
  • Book: Aristotle on the Uses of Contemplation
  • Online publication: 11 May 2018
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108363341.011
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Bibliography
  • Matthew D. Walker
  • Book: Aristotle on the Uses of Contemplation
  • Online publication: 11 May 2018
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108363341.011
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Bibliography
  • Matthew D. Walker
  • Book: Aristotle on the Uses of Contemplation
  • Online publication: 11 May 2018
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108363341.011
Available formats
×